Dramatic Approaches to Creative Fidelity: A Study in the Theater and Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel (1889-1973)
- Apply
- Visit
- Give
- Admissions
- Academics
- Programs
- Student Success
- Bachelor's Programs
- Accounting
- Analytics and Technology
- Applied Mathematics
- Art Minor
- Biology
- Business Administration (General Concentration)
- Engineering & Computing
- Business Communication
- Department of Mathematics
- Catholic Studies
- Modern Languages
- Chemistry
- Civil Engineering
- Communication
- Communication Sciences and Disorders
- Computer Science
- Corporate Accounting & Finance
- Criminal Justice
- Cybersecurity
- Economics
- Educational Studies
- Electrical Engineering
- Elementary Education
- English
- Environmental Studies
- Exercise Science
- Film Studies Minor
- Financial Markets & Economic Analysis
- French
- German
- Health Science
- History
- International Business
- Leadership Development Minor
- Management
- Marketing
- Marketing Analytics
- Mechanical Engineering
- Medical Humanities Minor
- Medical Laboratory Sciences
- Medical Spanish
- Music
- Nonprofit Leadership
- BSN
- Peace and International Studies
- Philosophy
- Physics
- Physics of Medicine
- Political Science
- Psychology
- Public Policy
- RN-BSN
- Secondary Education
- Sociology
- Spanish
- Special Education
- Sport Management
- Statistics Minor
- Theatre Arts
- Theology and Religious Studies
- Theology Teaching
- Women, Gender, and Sexuality Studies
- Pre-Dentistry
- Pre-Law
- Pre-Medicine
- Pre-Optometry
- Pre-Pharmacy
- Pre-Physician Assistant
- Pre-Veterinary Medicine
- Graduate
- Online
- Schools
- College of Arts and Sciences
- College of Business and Technology
- Saint Luke's™ College of Nursing and Health Sciences
- Academic Support
- Academic Advising
- Aylward-Dunn Learning Center
- Greenlease Library
- Honors Program
- Registrar
- Study Abroad
- Resources
- Academic Integrity
- Center for Service Learning
- Advanced College Credit Program
- Commencement
- Course Schedules
- Institutional Review Board
- University Press
- Humanities
- RU-KCU Early Acceptance Program
- Campus Life
- Alumni
- Athletics
- About
by
Katharine Rose Hanley
Introduction by
Paul Ricoeur
ii
University Press of America
© K.R.Hanley 1997
i
Acknowledgements of kind help and encouragement:
To the Officers of the international association Présence de Gabriel
Marcel,
To Monsieur and Madame Jean-Marie Marcel for their cordial friendship
and most helpful patronage,
To Madame Jeanne Parain-Vial for her special friendship and her
encouraging support of my projects,
To Professor Paul Ricoeur for his longstanding friendship and his
gracious kindness in providing an introduction for this work,
To Madame Bernadette Gradis and Monsieur Joël Bouëssée, officers
of the Foundation Européene de la Culture, for their gracious
recognition and promotion of my work,
To Le Moyne College Committee on Faculty Research for several
important financial grants in support of this study,
To Dr. Taisto Niemi, Le Moyne College Librarian (1963-81), whose vision
and kindness lent support to my research efforts and projects of the
Gabriel Marcel Institute for Existential Drama,
To Ms. Theresa Santillo, Administrative Assistant, Le Moyne College
Library for her help in procuring texts by Gabriel Marcel,
ii
Acknowledgment of kind help and encouragement continued:
To the Director and Personnel of Le Moyne College Audio Visual
Department, Professor Thomas Hogan and his staff for their excellent
technical services and generous cooperation,
To the officers and members of the Gabriel Marcel Institute for
Existential Drama for their excellent spirit and theatrical productions,
To Mireille Goodisman and Christiane Moloney for their helpful
suggestions and assurance that I could communicate in French--with
a little help from my friends,
To Professor and Mrs. G. Charles Paikert who so graciously encouraged
my intellectual and international adventures,
To Andrea Adams McKnight, whose energies and businesslike efficiency
helped immeasurably in materializing this text,
To Alan Clark for the service of his editorial skills,
To Stephen Healy for his artful illustrations depicting the commemorative
medal struck for the International Society Présence de Gabriel
Marcel.
To my family and all my dear friends who loved me and prayed for me,
thereby helping this project to come to fruition.
iii
Acknowledgment of permission to print:
Révue Philosophique de Louvain, permission to print an English
version, Chapter II. The Unfathomable : A Search for Presence, of an
article originally published in French "Réflexions sur la présence comme
signe d’
immortalité d'
après la pensée de Gabriel Marcel," Révue
Philosophique de Louvain tome 74, mai 1976, pp. 211-34.
Société Française de Philosophie, permission to print an
English version, Chapter III. "The Lantern: and The Light of Truth," an
article originally entitled Le Fanal et la fidélité creatrice," published in the
Bulletin de la Société française de Philosophie, avril-juin 1984, 78 annee,
No. 2, pp. 50-53.
World Congress of Philosophy, for permission to reprint Chapter
IV. "Dot the I : An Existential Witness of the Light of Truth." Originally
printed in the Acts of the XVIIth World Congress of Philosophy: Culture
and Nature Montreal, Canada, August 21-27, 1983.
Association des sociétés de philosophie de langue française for
permission to print an English version, Chapter VI. The Rebellious Heart:
and Human Creation, originally published in French as "Le Cœur des
autres et la création humaine" in La Création, Actes du XXe congrés de
L’Association des sociétés de philosophie de langue française, Quebec,
Canada, 20-23 aout 1984, L’Université de Quebec àTrois-Riviéres; and
an English version, Chapter IX. ""Rome is no longer in Rome: the
Challenge for Creative Incarnations of Fidelity," of Rome n’est plus dans
Rome et lavenir
des valeurs" presented in French and printed in
L’
Avenir, Actes du XXIe congr‘es de L’
Association des sociétés
philosophiques de langue française, August 21-24, 1986, Athens,
Greece.
American Catholic Philosophical Association for permission to
reprint the text of Chapter VII. "Colombyre or the Torch of Peace: the
Role of Person-Communities in Living Creative Fidelity to Values,
originally published under the title: "Dramatic Approaches to Creative
Fidelity" in Ethical Wisdom East and/or West: Proceedings of The
American Catholic Philosophic Association, Vol LI, Washington, D.C.,
1977, pp. 193 - 99; and to reprint the text of Chapter VIII. "The Sting:
Threatening the Foundations of Fidelity" of which an earlier version
appeared in the Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical
Association, Vol. LX, Washington, D.C., 1986.
iv
Table of Contents
Table of Contents iv
INTRODUCTION ix
FOREWARD xii
PART ONE: GABRIEL MARCEL. PHILOSOPHER-DRAMATISTMUSICIAN
1
Chapter I. An Introduction to Gabriel Marcel's Philosophic Quest 2
MUSIC 3
THEATER 5
Theater of Interiority 7
Theater for a Broken World 9
Theater of Inquiry 12
Theater Introduces Philosophy 15
Philosophy 19
Concrete Approach 20
A Call to Be 20
Neo-Socratic 21
Phenomenological 21
PROPER RELATIONS BETWEEN THEATER AND PHILOSOPHY 23
Always Prospective and Concretizing 24
Paradox of Philosopher-Dramatist 25
Chronological Bibliography Of Works By Gabriel Marcel About His Theater 41
Bibliography Of Works On Gabriel Marcel That Clarify The Nature Of His
Theater And Its Relationship To His Philosophy 45
PART TWO: DRAMATIC APPROACHES TO CREATIVE FIDELITY 55
Chapter II, The Unfathomable: A Search for Presence 56
Chapter III. The Lantern: and The Light of Truth 79
Chapter IV. Dot The I: An Existential Witness of the Light of Truth 91
v
Notes to Chapter IV. Dot the I and Existential Witness to the Light of Truth 97
1. Gabriel Marcel, The Existential Background of Human Dignity, Cambridge,
MA, Harvard University Press, 1963, p.179. 97
2. Les points sur les I, Paris, Editions Grasset, 1936.
97
Chapter VI. The Double Expertise: Fidelity and Infidelity 112
Chapter VII. Colombyre or the Torch of Peace: The Role of PersonCommunities
in Living Creative Fidelity to Values. 131
Chapter VIII. The Sting: Threatening the Foundations of Fidelity 140
Chapter IX. Rome Is No Longer In Rome: Challenge for Creative Incarnations
of Fidelity 156
Chapter X. Conclusion: Sketch of the Essential Features Highlighted 168
PART THREE: RESOURCES FOR RESEARCH 178
Works by Gabriel Marcel in Chronological Order of Composition with Publisher
References 179
A.Philosophical Works 179
B. Gabriel Marcel's Plays 183
C. Translations of Gabriel Marcel Plays into English. 184
C. Drama Criticism 186
E. Musical Compositions 188
E. Combination Works by Gabriel Marcel 199
F. Bibliographies 201
Lapointe, Francois H., "A Bibliography of the writings of Gabriel Marcel," pp.
583-609, in The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, (The Library of Living
Philosophers, Vol. XVII),ed. P. A. Schilpp and L. E. Hahn, LaSalle, IL:
Open Court, 1984. 201
H. Centers of Research 204
INDEX 205
vi
vii
"Being is an affirmation
of which
I am the stage
rather than the subject."
G. Marcel, The Philosophy of Existentialism, p. 18
viii
ix
INTRODUCTION
Katharine Rose Hanley has given herself the double task of
introducing English-speaking audiences to Gabriel Marcel’s theater and
of showing how theater and philosophy complement one another in
Marcel'
s work. I can attest that this book by Professor Hanley fulfills that
double promise.
As to the first task that the author assigned herself, it is quite
remarkable that she did not limit herself to merely stating in general terms
that the dramatic work of Gabriel Marcel introduces questioning that the
philosophic work continues, using conceptual analysis. She shows in
detail, through a judicious choice of several highly representative plays,
how the intrigue and development of the characters propose in each
instance a clearly defined enigma that calls for an effort of thought that
members of the audience can, if they wish, pursue under the guidance of
a philosophic essay easily identifiable in the master'
s work. Thus the
preoccupation with the presence of a loved one among the living after his
or her death--in The Unfathomable and in The Lantern --is followed up by
a philosophic reflection in "Presence and Immortality." Likewise, the
question posed by Dot the I is to know the meaning of living in the light of
truth: is it according to childlike simplicity or with adult sophistication? The
Rebellious Heart opens up the question of authentic creation, principally
in art. The Double Expertise introduces the question of fidelity in
interpersonal relationships, and so forth. On this topic, one point struck
me particularly in the detailed analyses of the plays selected, namely
what one might call the heuristic function of the final scene, and even at
times the last exchange between the characters. The last scene most
often serves the dual function of terminating the dramatic action and
beginning the philosophic reflection. More precisely, this nexus between
the dramatic closure and the opening of speculation differs from one play
to the next. In order to chart a course amid the profusion of dramatic
"conclusions," one can very easily follow the lead idea adopted by
Professor Hanley to explore the relation between theater and philosophy,
namely the theme of creative fidelity. One could also try situating the
various dramatic endings on a single scale, as Victor Goldsmith has done
in the past for the Dialogues of Plato, according to whether "the
conclusion" of the dialogue was nearer to the pole of unresolved enigma,
of aporia, or the pole of episteme, of certain truth. The case could be the
x
same for the dramatic endings of Gabriel Marcel's plays. On an axis
defined by the title in French of a collection of essays that is referred to
most frequently in this study— Du Refus à l’Invocation (From Refusal to
Invocation), translated with the English title of Creative Fidelity, certain
endings only witness negatively and as if by default, in favor of a "creative
presence"; then it is the impasse in which the characters are trapped that
invites spectators to follow at their own risk and peril the investigation of the
ways that the characters in the play did not know, could not, or would not
explore. Such is the situation of The Rebellious Heart and its final note of
mute despair. At the other end of the spectrum, we find plays where the
liberating word is clearly spoken; these are the plays of which Gabriel
Marcel could say that they anticipated his reflection, even at times his
conversion, or in any event the formulation of a "problem" on the point of
turning itself into a "mystery." Such is the case with The Unfathomable and,
up to a point, The Lantern with its ending that is both surprising and
ambiguous. It is a scale of creativity that one would have to speak of in the
case of Gabriel Marcel. But that scale is not, as for the Dialogues of Plato, a
scale of knowledge, but a scale of mystery. Between the two poles of "refusal"
and "invocation" are situated plays in which the accent is placed on threat
and challenge; such is the case of The Sting and Rome is No Longer in Rome,
plays with a decidedly pessimistic turn.
In fact, all the plays draw their dramatic quality, not only from the
opposition between the characters but from the ambivalence of the
responses that one or another character gives to the threat or the challenge
that distinguishes each of the Marcel plays. In that sense, the "refusal" or
the "invocation" designates not so much extreme poles as spiritual directions
that are opposite but equally operative. This is why our image of a scale
along which the plays of Gabriel Marcel would distribute themselves in a
hierarchical order is finally deceptive and must be abandoned after it has
rendered the didactic service we sought from it. We should speak rather of a
dramatic constellation, even an archipelagic formation (to approximate the
magnificent title: "the secret is in the isles”). The remark applies especially to
the plays that we have situated midway, and in which neither pure despair nor
total light prevails starkly, but an ambiguous, even elusive or ironic, end, if not a
satirical one as in The Double Expertise, or one with a nostalgic note as in
Colombyre or the Torch of Peace. It is here that the uniqueness of the
dramas requires an image less linear, if one may say so, more arborescent,
of the plays in half-tones. By the same fact, the reflection that the dramatic
conclusion calls for is different in each case; the very words of "creative fidelity,"
of "light of truth," of "presence" should lose their air of vague generality to
designate in each case a singular response to a singular challenge.
xi
This last remark leads me to the philosophic side of Professor Hanley's
book. If it is true, as she demonstrates, that the principal themes of Gabriel
Marcel's philosophy maintain an organic relationship with the dramatic
situation, one cannot characterize "second reflection" without an explicit
reference to the theater, if one understands by "second reflection" a
recollection on the conceptual level of the fundamental experiences of
"presence," of "fidelity," of "invocation," etc., beyond the objectivations that a
first reflection brings to them, whether the latter be of Cartesian, Kantian, or
Husserlian origin. It is not sufficient to say. that philosophy prolongs a
reflection that a member of the audience may have begun once the curtain
has fallen on the play. One must go as far as to say that second reflection
conserves, on its own proper level, something of the dramatic structure of the
plays. My earlier allusion to the Dialogues of Plato is pertinent here in
another sense, one highlighted by the designation of "neo-Socratic" that
Gabriel Marcel himself accepted for his work. Second reflection, I will say in
following the insistent suggestion of Professor Hanley, is itself of a structure
that is radically dialogical letter (conflict included). If the
philosophical essays of Gabriel Marcel appear often disconcerting, that is
because the reader wants to go directly to the theses that could constitute a
great Marcelian monologue. The reader simply finds the comings and goings
of a thought that advances only at the cost of incessant corrections. These
rectifications are nothing but the reflective transposition of an interplay of
questions and answers among virtual protagonists in a discussion. It is the
first objectifying reflection that is monological. The second reflection is
dialogical, not for any pedagogical concern, but by its essence. Gabriel
Marcel reflecting becomes himself the living theater where multiple voices
respond to one another within a discourse that appears to be spoken by one
voice only. In this sense, Professor Hanley was truly inspired in placing as
introductory quotation this statement by Gabriel Marcel: "Being is an
affirmation of which I am the stage rather than the subject." This stage is
indeed the scene for the theater of thought. Reflection remains a
continuation of theater to the extent that it assumes the logic of the question
and answer, such as Gadamer, following Collingwood, articulates it. The
interpersonal dialogue becomes the dialogue of the soul with itself, according
to the beautiful definition, of thought given in the Theatetus. That's why it is
not astonishing that dialogical reflection obeys as does dramatic dialogue,
the double gravitation of despair and of invocation. It is in this manner that
philosophy develops a "concrete approach to the ontological mystery."
It is in this exchange between the explorative character of the theater
and the dialogical character of the philosophy that is founded, in Gabriel
xii
Marcel's work, in the complementarity between the theater and philosophy.
That complementarity Professor Hanley goes well beyond affirming in
general terms, she establishes it in full detail in her excellent analyses of
several of the best plays of our common master-teacher, Gabriel Marcel.
Paul Ricoeur
FOREWARD
This work stands as a tribute to Gabriel Marcel. Its purpose is to share
with readers some idea of the interest that can accrue from the interaction of
an individuals thinking with Marcel's writings in theater and in philosophy.
Three encounters with Gabriel Marcel have greatly influenced my
personal and philosophic life. After a lecture given at Louvain University in
Belgium in 1958, Marcel autographed a copy of The Decline of Wisdom for
me.(1) Although the question he asked me on that occasion was a quite
xiii
practical ore "who are you?" its cogency, along with the personally engaging
look in his eyes, makes it a vivid question for me every time I recall that
incident.
During his lecture tour around the United States in 1965, Marcel visited
Le Moyne College and received an honorary doctoral degree. At the end of his
five-day visit to Syracuse, he inscribed a copy of Creative Fidelity for me, "in
remembrance of an encounter which I hope will one day be renewed."(2)
Just three weeks before his death on October 8, 1973, at the conclusion of
a conversation after luncheon in his home in Paris, Gabriel Marcel inscribed
Five Major Plays for me, affirming "a bond of spiritual kinship that once
renewed would not be broken."(3)
Many other people can relate similar happenings, for Marcel had a gift of
powerful personal Présence that touched friends and readers alike. It is my
hope for those who read this book, that Marcel will became a friend, one with
whom a bond of spiritual kinship develops, one who leaves a deep and
lasting influence upon their lives.
Several months after Marcel's death, I was among those invited to
speak at De Paul University's Day of Commemorative Tribute, February 4,
1974. I wanted to communicate some perspectives from my last
conversation with Gabriel Marcel. yet the challenge for me was to make
these recollections alive and meaningful to people who were not present at
that particular and very moving moment when Marcel talked of presence
from beyond death. Quite fortunately I thought of his book, Presence and
Immortality. (4) Not only its subject, but also its format were just what was
needed. This book combines, in one volume, the first act of an unfinished
play, journal entries from the years 1938-1943, and philosophic essays, all
focusing on one common topic.
In preparing that talk, I realized that theater enables spectators to enter
into a concrete life situation wherein a mystery reveals itself to those whose
lives are touched by its impact. Thus each person can be caught up in a
situation where certain questions are explored and certain perspectives of
insight come to light. In the case of The Unfathomable (5), the fact that
Maurice Lechevalier is officially reported as missing in action significantly
affects the lives of various members of his family. Their reactions and
interpretations differ according to the relationship each had had with Maurice
before his disappearance.
xiv
The dramatic presentation enables audiences to enter into the situation
where a loved one, a family member, a friend, or a mere acquaintance dies or
otherwise disappears from the daily scene and the familiar ways of
interacting. The dramatization of this event raises questions clearly and
poignantly. What has become of the loved one who has passed on? What
will become of the bereaved, the loved one left behind? Is survival of loved
ones beyond death possible? Can the bereaved continue to live on without the
idea that the loved one still actively intervenes in their lives even from beyond
death and that the gifts of the loved one'
s presence are still received? These
questions occur, not merely theoretically but as real alternatives, dramatic
heart-rending speculations that can touch and radically alter our lives.
Inquiry about these questions, and research about the various possible
answers that will drastically affect our lives, are pursued as these issues
engage our o w n personal being. that is at stake in a determination of the
emptiness or fullness of our own lives. The questions and the way they are
treated are truly existential. The dramatic action brings into clear focus
questions arousing the interest and speculation of members of the audience
about their own relationships, as well as those of characters in the play.
This discovery of how Marcel'
s theater lets many people come into
personal and experiential contact with a reality that calls for reflection and
clarification in their own lives, as well as in the lives depicted on the stage, was
not only significant for that particular day of commemorative tribute. It revealed
to me an approach for entering into dialogue with Marcel's thought, an
approach that has remained significant for whatever subsequent study I
have undertaken.
After that event, I began collecting and studying Marcel'
s thirty plays. I
also collected the numerous articles he wrote as a drama critic, as well as
essays and lectures wherein he comments on the nature of his existential
theater and at times clarifies its relationship to his philosophic reflections.
In conjunction with metaphysics classes and seminars on the theater of
Gabriel Marcel, The Gabriel Marcel Institute for Existential Drama at Le
Moyne College has produced seven plays on stage, for television, and as
readers' theater adaptations: The Rebellious Heart, 1975; The Lantern, 1976;
The Double Expertise, 1977; Dot the I, 1978; A Man of God, 1978; The
Broken World, 1979; and Colombyre or the Torch of Peace,1980.(6) Similar
productions have occurred at other colleges and universities, and always
with noteworthy benefits.
xv
This hands-on experience of producing Gabriel Marcel'
s plays, plus
the opportunity for seminars studying his theater as a way of access to
his philosophic thought, provided more than ample evidence that the
approach of studying dramatic works as a gateway to philosophic
reflection was as exciting and perhaps more illuminating even than
Marcel'
s commentaries had suggested.
In 1983-1984 a series of invitations to lecture before various
prestigious audiences afforded me the opportunity to articulate the thesis
that Marcel'
s theater and philosophy should be studied together. This
series of lectures also enabled me to flesh out an illustration of how this
method of study allows us to clarify some essential features of creative
fidelity, a key theme in Marcel'
s life and work.
This book is the fruit of these various moments of encounter,
theater production, philosophic reflection, and dialogue. The work
includes three parts: an introduction to Gabriel Marcel'
s theater, a study
of eight pairings of plays and essays that clarify various aspects and
dimensions of creative fidelity, and a section of information helpful for
those interested in knowing more about Gabriel Marcel'
s life and work.
The tone of this book is largely conversational, perhaps emulating
somewhat the style of Marcel'
s writing and thought. Chapters Two
through Nine are derived from lectures delivered on various occasions.
Some of these presentations have already been published elsewhere
either in English or in French.
It is my hope that this work will concretely suggest some of the
advantages to be gleaned from studying Marcel'
s theater on its own as
theater, and also as a privileged gateway into the realm of his
philosophic reflections.
It is also my hope that this book and the approach it suggests will
appeal to students and teachers in interdisciplinary and humanities
courses. I am sure the book will help all who desire a concrete approach
to and a personal involvement in philosophic investigations. It may also
prove to be of interest and benefit to theater people who will find Marcel'
s
existential theater profound in pact and accessible not merely to a restricted
intellectual elite, but rather to all who have a sensitivity of spirit to
compassionately live the heights and the depths of human experience as
these are being portrayed in the lives of members of the human family.
xvi
Finally it is my hope that this book of meditations on various aspects of creative
fidelity will entice readers to seek directly and personally fresh insights into the rich
values of human life that Marcel's works bring to light.
This work will have succeeded and fulfilled my expectations for it if it sends readers
directly to the writings of Gabriel Marcel, and lets the concrete approach of theater open
up the way of access to philosophic reflection and insight whose motherlode is deep
and rich.
Katharine Rose Hanley
xvii
Notes to the Author’s Foreword.
Books by Gabriel Marcel mentioned in the Foreword:
1. The Decline of Wisdom, London, Harvill Press, 1954; New York,
Philosophical Library, 1955.
2. Creative Fidelity, New York, Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1964;
New York, Crossroad Press, 1982.
3. (Five Major Plays), Cinq Pieces Majeures, Paris, Plon, 1973.
4. Presence and Immortality, Pittsburgh, PA., Duquesne
University Press, 1967.
5. The Unfathomable, pp. 254-84 in Presence and Immortality, cited
above.
6. The Rebellious Heart and The Broken World with an Introduction by
the author appeared in The Existential Drama of Gabriel Marcel,
Francis J. Lescoe, St. Jos. College, West Hartford, CT, McAuley
Institute, 1974.
The Lantern appeared in Cross Currents, Spring 1958; Two Plays by
Gabriel Marcel, Lanham:MD, University Press of America, 1988.
A Man of God appeared in Three Plays by Gabriel Marcel,_ New
York, Hill and Wang, 1965.
T w o One Act Plays by Gabriel Marcel: Dot the I and The Double
Expertise, Lanham, MD., University Press of America, 1986.
Colombyre or the Torch of Peace, translated by Joseph Cunneen, is
an English version of the original French Colombyre ou le brasier de
la paix, published with Le Divertissement posthume, La Double
Expertise et Les points sur les I, in Théâtre comique, Paris, Albin
Michel, 1947.
English titles for works by Gabriel Marcel that have not yet been
published in English are not underlined.
xviii
PART ONE:
GABRIEL MARCEL.
PHILOSOPHER-DRAMATIST-MUSICIAN
2
Chapter I. An Introduction to Gabriel Marcel's Philosophic
Quest
Gabriel Marcel is principally known to an English-speaking
audience as a philosopher, an existential thinker of international
renown. He was also a playwright whose dramas were staged in major
theaters in Paris, and also in Belgium, Germany, the United States, and
elsewhere. When Marcel gave the William Janes Lectures at Harvard
.
University in 1961, some twelve years after presenting the Gifford
Lectures in Aberdeen, Scotland, he expressed the hope that an
English-speaking audience would soon no longer know his theater only
in an abstract way but would have a direct and concrete experience of
its performance.(1) Marcel was also an accomplished musician,
improvising and writing piano compositions, often bringing favorite
poems to full expression as songs.(2)
In a talk sponsored by the Alliance Française, Marcel noted that
for him music, theater, and philosophy were like three concentric rings,
or concentric levels of communication. Music is the innermost and
deepest center; theater is next, with its dialogue among incarnate
persons; and philosophy is the outermost and last, with its discussion in
general terms of questions and challenges affecting the meaning of
human life.(3) He also wrote in 1962 that unlike past readers who first
approached his philosophy, in the future those who wish to fathom his
thought would have to conceive the theater in relation to the music, and
the philosophy in relation to the theater. He even added that those with
a sensitivity to music will have a special advantage.(4)
These remarks suggest that the interrelationship of music,
theater, and philosophy may provide a significant clue as to how to
approach Gabriel Marcel'
s thought. These comments, while clear,
remain quite succinct. Marcel does not explain their sense; rather he
leaves to us the task of reflecting to clarify their meaning.
The deploying of this image will be the leitmotif of this essay,
which will also highlight some of the distinctive features of Marcel's work
and suggest the importance of letting his theater serve as channel to his
philosophic reflection.
3
MUSIC
Music played a dominant role in Marcel's life and for a time he
considered a career as a concert pianist. He often wrote about music,
and even improvised musical compositions, most often to give some of
his favorite poems their full expression in song. A commemorative
medal struck after his death shows his likeness with his dates of birth
and death (1889-1973) on one side; on the other side is a figure of
Orpheus with the caption, "Availability, fidelity, hope."(5)
Marcel once wrote that if he had to select a character from
mythology to typify his own life, he would have to choose Orpheus, so
central was the role of music in his life. He even spoke of his marriage,
about which he was always discrete, as being under the sign of music,
pure joy. His wife was an accomplished musician who worked with him,
annotating his musical compositions. Marcel also wrote that in his early
years it was music that provided for him the presence and assurance
of the sacred in human life.(6)
Music not only played an important role in Marcel'
s life, it also
remains a significant metaphor revealing the kind of knowledge and
communication he hoped for. Music is present to us personally,
affecting each individual according to his or her sensitivity to hear.
Music moves us integrally, touching us bodily and spiritually and
influencing our feelings and consciousnesses. Marcel wanted ideas to
be realistically founded, rooted in encounters with realities as personally
experienced in concrete incarnate situations involving our feelings, our
attitudes, and our persons as well as our rational consciousnesses.
Music reveals in a privileged way the dimension of life that Marcel's
searchings bring to light, a spiritual dimension without which our lives
would lack a level of humanness, dignity, and depth.(7) Marcel was
concerned with the sacred in human life and he found witnesses to it in
the works of Bach, Beethoven, Mozart, and others. He was curious to
conceive of how these sacred realities can be encountered by us. In
his "Essay in Autobiography" he wrote that it was a central
preoccupation of his thought to explore how a transcendent
dimension of life can be present to an individual.(8) Music llustrates
a response to that question. Music, like many realities we experience
bodily and spiritually, is present to us in our individual subjectivity by
way of inwardness and depth.(9) Music is reality that can be present to
many individuals and to each one by way of interiority and depth.
4
Finally, music, by its presence, effects a certain assurance of the
message it conveys.
For Marcel, music is significant in its own right as a mode of
communication; it is also present in his dramatic and philosophic works
both directly by explicit reference and indirectly by its influence on his
style of composition. References to Strauss waltzes, music of
Solesmes, and Beethoven sonatas and symphonies have their own
peculiar resonance in the context of the plays in which they occur.
Music appears as a central theme in several plays, (Quartet in F#), (My
Time is not Your Time), and (The Sting). Music figures as a secondary
theme in others, for example, Ariadne and (Increase and Multiply).
Music is also present directly or by allusion in The Unfathomable, The
Broken World, (Grace), Colombyre or the Torch of Peace, in fact, in
almost all of his plays.(10) Marcel'
s dramatic works reveal an
architectonic structure similar to that of musical compositions. His
dramas show the influence of a musical style of composition in the
development of dramatic situations, and in the denouement that often
ends on a note of dissonance.(11) One can also recognize the style of
one who improvises and composes musically in the way his thought
progresses in his philosophic writings.
These reflections on music as the first and innermost of three
concentric layers of communication should alert us to the fact that
Marcel expects each person who philosophizes about the human
condition to root his or her reflections in an experiential awareness of
those realities as they can be encountered by way of inwardness
and depth. Marcel offers the encouragement that those initiated to
the deep secrets of the art of music may be more apt to follow the
transposition to other modes of consciousness that theater and
philosophy effect. If we heed Marcel'
s important remarks in the
Préface to Kenneth Gallagher'
s very fine book, The Philosophy of
Gabriel Marcel, "that whoever approaches my work will have to
conceive the drama in function of music, and the philosophy in
function of drama ,"(12) we may indeed expect to see the drama as a
way of leading us into a world of darkness and light wherein we
encounter important existential questions, not only on stage but
within the theater of our own inwardness and depth.
While Marcel wrote only a few succinct, though cogent,
statements about the role of music in his life and work, he wrote
5
numerous commentaries about the significance of his theater in
itself and as a gateway to his philosophic writings.(13)
THEATER
Marcel writes about his reaction to the theater, which was his
first vocation and for a while, he thought, his only one. His way of
conceiving questions is through a dramatic imagination that
envisages people caught up in a situation of conflict. From the time
he was a child he was at home in the world of theater. He reveled in
creating imaginary characters who peopled the otherwise lonely
landscape of his universe as an only child. A play he wrote at age
twelve was favorably evaluated by a critic and was later produced in a
modified version as A Man of God. (14) Marcel had a real gift for
dramatic composition and a predilection for theater. He enjoyed
hearing his father read plays aloud to him and in later years they
delighted in attending theater performances together. He noted that
theater seemed to gratify the exigency they shared for the aesthetically
pleasing coupled with an intellectual rigor.
Marcel worked for more than forty years as a drama critic, writing
for prestigious reviews. In 1923 he was named drama critic for L'
Europe
Nouvelle. He also wrote for Sept, Temps Present, La Vie intellectuelle,
and others. In 1944 he was named drama critic for Nouvelles
Littéraires. He wrote numerous articles and essays and three full-length
books of drama criticism.(15) All this he did in addition to being a
playwright who created some thirty play's that appeared from 1911 to
1961. One of his plays, The Lantern, remains in the permanent
repertory of the Comédie Française and his work received
numerous French and international awards.(16)
Marcel acknowledged that theater enabled him to break a path
for freedom in his own life, a life that, though gifted and privileged in
many ways, was also marked by tragedy and loss. Furthermore,
through the immediate milieu of his family he became aware of the
suffering wrought by fundamental conflicts. Dramatic imagination let
Marcel see these antinomies played out in the light of the theater
and deal with them in his own life, thus gaining greater lucidity and
freedom. We can understand that Marcel creates his theater with the
hope that it may help others to recognize and deal with some of the
6
fundamental questions and conflicts in their lives, and thus attain
greater freedom for themselves.
Marcel saw that his was a theater of consciousness, one of
dawning light that opens up paths for freedom to explore. For him,
theater is the second, more exteriorized circle of communication. His
theater, like his music, deals with tensions and conflicts around various
themes. While his dramas depict the playing out of life'
s conflicts and
antinomies as these can lead to despair, they also convey the
possibility of moving beyond them in hope. If we heed Marcel'
s dictum
that his theater is to be conceived as a function of music, we will not be
surprised to discover that his theater in its own proper way also leads
audiences to a depth of their hearts where they experience a certain
call to be. Both music and drama work through the tension of opposition
that conflict brings, and Marcel'
s theater, like his music, moves toward
some kind of resolution, even one that may end on a note of dissonance.
Music moves us through this experience on a level of inward listening that is
beyond eris (verbal argumentation). Theater lets the theme play itself out in the
more externally manifest expression of incarnate subjectivities and their more
verbal form of interpersonal dialogue. Yet theater, like music, enables us to open
onto perspectives of .light and hope that reveal themselves to us as we live
through the tragic, transcending it by way of a path of interiority that leads to the
deepest center in our selves.
Theater presents a living world concretely: lights, music, decor are set on
stage with live actors and actresses. As Marcel wrote in (The Secret is in
the Isles), the medium of theater lets spectators jump right into the life world the
drama portrays. Theatrical presentation permits audiences to be caught
up in the dramatic action occurring on stage and to live it not only as affecting the
characters of the play but also as engaging the very being of the spectator.
Theater is such a complete mode of communication that it allows for this kind
of total participation, even inviting personal identification with what is being
enacted on stage.(17)
Marcel's plays are imaginatively conceived, well crafted, and artfully
structured. They are also dramatically powerful. They usually depict
domestic situations, with settings and themes familiar to all of us. He presents
a drama with which we can easily identify. In this, as well as in a certain
characteristic style involving suspense, surprise turns of events, and
unexpected shocking developments, Marcel's plays are not unlike sate of the
"soaps" popular on television today. Marcel's plays depict situations wherein
there are issues about identity and desire for communication and love.
7
They show challenges to fidelity and situations involving infidelity. Some
explore the tensions of political differences and examine the struggle of
individual conscience. Others portray the generation gap, concern for
soldiers missing in action, and fears before the menace of war. Still other
dramas explore individuals'
struggles for success and authenticity, or deal
with questions about faith, music, artistic integrity, survival, and life after death.
Marcel'
s plays focus on aspects of human life that are of concern. (18)
As these plays present domestic settings, with family and friends trying to
cane to grips with crises over fundamental issues plaguing their
relationships, they bring to light questions that confront individuals who
are curious about whether or not there is a sense to their lives.
Several features of Marcel'
s dramatic art enable audiences to come
to a vivid and personal awareness of some of these basic issues.
The characters of Marcel'
s plays and their personal
relationships seem to be the focus of the dramatic action. Marcel
has a real forte for creating characters who are lifelike, whom we
feel we'
ve meet or whom we'
d certainly recognize if we did meet
them in real life. As these characters develop and reveal
themselves during the course of the play, the audience begins to
sense something of who these characters are and what they live by.
(19)
Theater of Interiority
Marcel'
s theater has been called "a theater of interiority."
Marcel himself once wrote that he knows and creates the characters
of his plays, as it were, "from within." Spectators then participating in
what dramatis personae are living on stage are moved to a deep
level of compassionate sensitivity within themselves as they identify
with the dawning of consciousness that occurs "within" characters in
the play.
As the play progresses and spectators become aware, not
only of the external events that are happening, but also of the
interior drama that the characters are living, there dawns a
consciousness of the tragic that is emerging in these peoples’ lives.
There is usually at least one person of striking lucidity or
remarkable sensitivity in Marcel's plays. These people project a
8
sense of the tragic in their situation. Sometimes this consciousness
is communicated directly, as in the case of the exceptionally lucid
and articulate Raymond Chavière in The Lantern. (20) In other
cases the characters themselves are not so translucent, but the
consciousness of the tragic in their life situation is reflected to the
audience by characters who themselves remain somewhat opaque
as in the case of Françoise in “Grace” (21)
This tragic consciousness is not so much a theoretical or an
intellectual awareness as it is an awareness that is enmeshed in a
concrete situation, one that is lived bodily and felt in terms of
sensitivity before it emerges on a level that can be articulated and
then reflected upon. Marcel observed that his was the paradoxical
situation of one who is a philosopher-dramatist. His theater is not a
theater of ideas as theoretic notions to be expounded and argued.
Neither is it a theater that proselytizes an ideology, or a showcase
for puppets who merely mouth an author’s convictions. Marcel
observed that any serious drama brings about a heightening of
consciousness.(22) His theater, however, assists at the birth of
consciousness in a distinctive way. In (The Invisible Threshold), Le
Seuil Invisible, in the Préface he wrote for his first published plays,
Marcel spoke of the dawning of a tragic consciousness) His dramas
present real people coming with almost palpable birthpangs to a lived
awareness of the tragic dimension in their life situation. In Marcel's
dramas his tragic awareness relates to the fundamental issues and
drama of human life.
Marcel'
s plays communicate not only ideas but also an awakening
of consciousness. Actors present the anguish they live. With lucidity and
compassion spectators can identify with the consciousness and drama
of interiority that characters on the stage are living. The action, with its
heightening of consciousness, is played out not only on the stage before
us but also on a stage within us, the intimate theater of each individual's
personal and deepening awareness.
Theater, like music, brings audiences to a deep personal center
within themselves. Theater and music also effect a searching concern
for a significant spiritual dimension in their lives. Both media affect the
person bodily as well as spiritually and in that manner permit an
awareness that is incarnate, holistic, and integral while being intensely
personal. In contrast to music, theater is more verbal. The argument of
conflict is more explicit, and the focus on a particular tragic dimension in
9
human life is sharpened. Incarnate portrayal facilitates audience
identification with the lead characters in the play, and dramatic action
heightens an increasingly explicit and articulated consciousness of the
precise tragic dimension in this particular life situation.
Marcel '
s dramas portray the shadowed side of life. Compared to
his music or his philosophy, his plays have a more somber tone, often
conveying the pathos that is part of life's tragic aspect. Still, even these
plays enable us to perceive a glimmer of light that invites us to explore
pathways to freedom. This occurs through a peculiar kind of
breakthrough or transcendence beyond the tragic.(24)
Theater for a Broken World
Marcel refers to his theater as a theater of a broken world. The
sentiment first found expression on the lips of Christiane Chesnay in her
conversation with Denise Furstlin in first act of the play the Broken
world. 'Don't you feel...that we are living...if you can call it living...in a
broken world? Yes, broken like a broken watch. The mainspring has
stopped working. Just look at it, nothing has changed. Everything is in
place. But put the watch to your ear, and you don'
t hear any ticking. You
know what I'm talking about, the world, what we call the world, the world
of human creatures. . .it seems to me it must have had a heart at one
time, but today you would say the heart had stopped beating..."(25)
In an introduction written for the publication of two plays, The
Rebellious Heart and The Broken world, Marcel observes that the
consciousness of a broken world takes a different form in each of
these plays. For Christiane in The Broken world, it is the world around
her that disintegrates and breaks apart. This was a world she'
d
constructed from a disillusioned level of herself. For Rose in The
Rebellious Heart, the breaking up of her world is manifest through a
gradual awareness of that breaking deepening in her heart.(26)
Marcel also acknowledges that "theater of a broken world" can
aptly be applied to the entire corpus of his dramatic works. In each of his
plays, as the lead characters became consciousness of the fact that their
world has fallen apart, a certain light also dawns for them. This light is
not an intellectual explanation, it is not necessarily even a conscious
awareness, but there occurs an illumination of a mysterious dimension
10
of their lives that transcends the tragic. In some instances the light is
somber, in others it is brighter--almost a light of hope in the darkness,
and in one or another exceptional case the light appears as a flash of
awareness that illuminates the entire landscape of their lives.(27)
In The Rebellious Heart Rose cried plaintively, "There is
but one suffering and that is to be alone."(28) Yet as the play comes to
its climax it becomes clear that the intense suffering in her life is not
caused by her aloneness but by the quality of the relationships she has
with others around her: a husband, Daniel, who uses her but who does
not appreciate her or really relate to her as a person; and a stepson,
John, taken from her by the selfishness of a father whose ways the son
will probably follow, for he has abdicated any real hope for happiness in
this life. As the play ends, heavy with the sadness of despair, there is an
aura of questioning. Perhaps the questions are quickened more in the
rebellious hearts of the audience than in the explicit consciousness of
the characters of the play. Couldn't something have been done to
provide for an understanding and communion of love between Rose
and Daniel? Couldn't John have been saved?
The Broken World ends with a light of hope flooding onto the final
scene of the broken world, when Christiane, who thought herself
rejected and incapable of ever finding true love or real happiness in this
life, by a strange change of circumstances finds that, contrary to what
she felt and believed, she has been and is really loved and not forsaken.
On the strength of this discovery, the realization awakens within her that
there is hope for love in her life. In humbly communicating this
experience to her husband, she invites him to live out with her the
realization of that hope.(29)
In "The Iconoclast," a play written in 1921, which Marcel also
mentions in this same introduction, the world is off-center because of the
death of Vivian, Jacques'
first wife. The world becomes more out of tune
when their friend, Abel, who had not expressed his passionate love for
Vivian out of respect for his good friend Jacques, learns that Jacques
has remarried. Fired by resentment, Abel feels that Jacques is
unworthy of a pure memory of his first marriage to Vivian, and so he
contrives to arouse Jacques'
suspicion about Vivian'
s fidelity. Abel, for
his part, is crushed when he later learns that it was Vivian'
s urging and
her express request that moved Jacques to remarry and to carry on living
after her death. Abel would now like to restore Jacques'
confidence in
Vivian's fidelity. The following quote from a commentary written twenty-
11
four years after the play speaks well of the opening onto mystery Marcel's
plays effected even before the author was consciously aware of this.
Abel, who has realized his own mistake, suddenly sees
the whole tragedy in its true light. He becomes aware
that, in a sense infinitely surpassing the still too physical
and crude image of her in Jacques'
mind, Vivian's
Présence remains with than. She is still there to draw
them together once more, but only by recognizing this
mystery can they create the harmony in which the soul
can at last possess itself. "You could never," says Abel
to Jacques, "be satisfied for long in a world deserted by
mystery...Life without mystery, would be stifling." But the
mystery must be approached with humility. As Abel says
again: "Life itself will confound the iconoclasts and the selfappointed
judges... Life, or He who is beyond words." And
now at last Jacques too--though as yet confusedly--feels
awakening like music in his soul the consciousness of this
fruitful peace. (30)
In "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," the essay from which this last
quote was taken, as well as in other critical essays, Marcel stresses the
importance of the final act, and especially the last scene of a play, both
for the unity they bring to the entire work and for the questions they
raise.(31)
Marcel'
s plays often end on a disquieting, dissonant note, with
surprises that leave audiences stunned. Yet the end of a Marcel play is
disquieting also for the kind of questions it raises, and for the way these
questions affect audiences.
One theater-goer commented that Marcel'
s dramas have a
haunting quality.(32) The characters and key moments of the drama
remain with the spectator long after the final curtain has fallen on stage.
Gradually the questions come to light, in terms of the situation and
interaction of the characters in the play, and also in reference to ones
own life situation. Furthermore, the questions now come to light in one'
s
own consciousness as one seeks to fathom their meaning and then find
an acceptable sense that can illuminate a path toward freedom in one's
own life.
12
The end of a Marcel play can indeed be very unsettling. These
plays do not have "and they lived happily ever after" endings. The
conflicts and the tensions of fundamental antinomies remain, though
they also are somehow transcended. The dramatic situation is not neatly
resolved like a problem that is solved when all the pieces of the puzzle
fall into place. The tragic remains but there also appears the light of a
pathway to one's freedom. Marcel's plays do not seek to explain, or
answer questions. They do not settle problems or resolve conflicts. The
role of the theater, the playwright states, is not to explain, it is to show.
What a Marcel play shows raises questions and opens pathways
for reflection to clarify then. These questions can be formulated clearly
and concretely in terms of the life situation of the characters in the play.
With this articulation of these questions the process of reflective
clarification already begins. Marcel Belay, an exceptionally fine critic of
Gabriel Marcel'
s theater, remarked that drama is already a first
reflection.(33) This first reflection can be followed up with the further
reflection of drama criticism, reconstructing the play in reverse by starting
with the questions raised after the curtain falls. Marcel'
s plays also invite
another form of ongoing reflection, a personal one that can eventually
become technically philosophical.
Theater of Inquiry
Marcel acknowledges that his theater is indeed a theater of
inquiry.(34) His dramatic imagination envisions situations wherein
characters are working through questions and challenges that flow from
the tension of fundamental conflicts. This dramatic development is
shown throughout the plays. His dramas conclude, having raised
certain questions that neither the play nor the playwright attempts to
explain.
These questions are latent throughout the play, but are brought
sharply into focus in the final moments of the last scene or the last act.
The audience is left with questions about the characters. What
becomes of them after the denouement of the drama? What do they do
next? Why didn'
t they act or react differently during the course of the
play? For example, a propos of The Rebellious Heart, does John
become a dandy ne'
er do well? Can'
t Rose convince Daniel to bring the
boy home and help him? Why doesn'
t Rose leave Daniel and make a
home for John? Why doesn'
t Rose refuse to be used merely as a
13
provider of tenderness, a subject for plays? Why doesn't she insist on
being loved for her true worth? Why doesn'
t Daniel understand, why
can'
t he see? Why doesn'
t she make him see? The tragedy is that these
people in this situation can'
t make it work. That tragic awareness is
stunning, and it leads to a deeper and broader level of questioning. Is a
genuine communion of love possible between Rose and any of her
intimates such as Daniel, her husband, or John, her adopted son? If a
communion of love is not possible, why not? This level of questioning
gives rise to another where the perspective broadens. Is a genuine
communion of love possible in my life or in any human life? What
attitudes and circumstances seem to prevent or destroy true love?
What attitudes and circumstances would be requisite for true love to
occur or endure? What is the nature of genuine human love? Can its
traits be recognized and its essential dimensions lived out effectively?
What is a human life worth, if love is possible or if it is not possible?
What is the worth of life if true love does not occur, if tragedy prevails?
What is the worth and sense of life if true love does grace people'
s
lives?
All of Marcel'
s plays, his comic as well as his tragic works, end by
raising questions in the hearts and minds of those who see them
performed and are touched by their drama. Each raises questions
about the characters, the situation, the play'
s motif and themes. Each
raises and leaves open with the spectators questions about a
paradoxical situation that affects fundamental aspects of their own lives
as well as the lives of the characters on stage. The questions Marcel's
theater brings to light are experienced as a fundamental call to be that
invites our free response and engages us personally, for they affect our
very lives and being.
The final scenes of Marcel plays open onto mystery. Gaston
Fessard, one of Marcel'
s finest critics, rightly affirmed that the hallmark
of Marcel'
s theater is its communication of mystery. (35)
This communication occurs in a distinctive manner. One of
Marcel'
s fortes is the creation of characters who live and move and
speak as "I'
s," as unique conscious subjectivities, characters whom the
author has created from within. Then, because the action of the play
allows these characters to reveal their growing consciousnesses, the
spectator has the opportunity to participate in the realities occurring in
their lives in a person-to-person encounter. Through dialogue and
action, and especially through the incarnate magic and art of the
14
theater that actors and actresses effect, the character reveals him or
herself as a person. The actor or actress manifests that person from
within, effecting what Marcel later and in another context called an
"existential witness." The person in the play becomes "present" for the
audience, communicating not only the words said but the very reality that
he or she is living. As the actors and actresses "presentify" what they
are living and even at tines what they live by, the audience can be
touched by the reality that is manifesting itself through the lives of the
people in the play. Thus in an effective way Marcel'
s drama
communicates an experience of mystery that touches people in the play
and in the audience alike.(36)
When a Marcel play comes to an end, the spectator has been
drawn into a conscious experience of the tragic and has also
encountered the presence of a mysterious dimension in the lives of the
people in the play. He or she has been drawn into the dramatic climax
that gives rise to questions, yet provides the wherewithal for ongoing
reflection, for it opens onto a dimension of mystery that invites inquiry and
offers a pathway of light. Thus freedom can begin to find a way as
people struggle to transcend the tragic in their lives.
Drama, like music, can lead audiences to an experiential
knowledge of some of the fundamental mysteries of life. Both music
and drama enable audiences to encounter these realities inwardly and
deeply. Still, drama communicates this awareness in a different manner
than music does. Drama'
s mode of communication is incarnate
interpersonal dialogue. Drama heightens our consciousness of the
tragic that can emerge from some of the fundamental antinomies in
human life. Drama brings audiences to the point of beginning to deal with
these issues in a consciously reflective, interrogative, and reasoned
fashion. Yet Marcel'
s dramas, like poetry and song, would have
audiences deal with these issues, not in an abstractly reasoned
fashion, but in a reasoned reflection that clarifies the concrete situation
of unique human beings. Marcel'
s dramas allow audiences to
experience the situations of others, to recognize the reality of these
situations as also their own, and to understand them with that blend of
sympathy and] intelligence that tragic pity evokes. Tragic pity enables us
to identify with the suffering of others and to compassionately
understand it from a central focal point deep within our own conscious
being.(37)
15
Theater Introduces Philosophy
Philosophy, as rational discourse expressed in general terms, is
the third and outermost ring among Marcel'
s three concentric circles of
communication. Yet if we heed Marcel'
s dictum that his philosophy
should be construed in relation to his theater, we shall see how Marcel'
s
theater provides a uniquely appropriate, if not indispensable, gateway
to his philosophic reflection.
Marcel'
s plays raise the questions upon which his philosophic
writings reflect. These questions are posed concretely as they arise in
the lives of real, individual persons. As the characters in a play are
brought to deal with these questions in their everyday lives, their
consciousness of them is heightened. This consciousness of the
questions is communicated dramatically to the audience, who can also
feel the weight of these issues affecting their o w n lives.
Marcel'
s theater poses these questions in a fortunate manner by
conscious subjects, who speak in the first person and ask about the
sense of their lives in view of the crises and conflicts that the dramatic
action brings to light. It is easy then for audiences to pose these
questions on their own account too, because they see their impact
spelled out concretely in the lives of persons whose situation is not
ultimately that different from their own. The fundamental issues that
give rise to the dramatic tensions and the consciousness of the tragic that
emerge in the play pertain to questions about the quality of
interpersonal relationships that these people have or fail to have with
one another. Marcel'
s theater brings members of the audience and
characters in the play alike to personal awareness of questions
affecting the quality or the lack of quality in their own individual lives
and in the relationships they have with others.
Marcel'
s theater is a privileged way of leading spectators to an
encounter with mystery. It is precisely this ability to bring people into the
Présence of the mysterious dimension of human life that is the hallmark of
Gabriel Marcel's theater. This ability to lead people through the tragic
aspect of consciousness to a dawning awareness of the Présence and
light of mystery makes Marcel'
s theater a uniquely privileged and
invaluable gateway to philosophic reflection.
For those who would study Marcel'
s thought, enter into dialogue with
it, or simply understand it there are definite advantages to following
16
Marcel'
s own example and guidance, adopting an approach that he
suggests and that he himself used.
There are significant benefits that can be gained from studying
Marcel'
s theater as a way of access to his philosophy. Marcel'
s plays not
only pose the questions that his philosophy later investigates, but his
theater enables the audience to personally encounter the mystery under
investigation. In addition to these signal advantages, Marcel'
s theater spells
out concretely and in terms of individual peoples lives the i m p a c t of the
issues under investigation,--be they war, peace, individual conscience, faith,
fidelity, generation gap, or other concerns. The plays also show the various
attitudes and stances that different people can adopt toward these issues.
In this respect Marcel'
s theater begins the process of reflective analysis and
interpretation that his philosophy later carries on in a more explicitly
reasoned and critical manner. Thus it is an entryway into Marcel'
s
philosophic thinking.
One who has experienced a Marcel play is moved by its dynamic on
a deep and lasting level. One is drawn toward a distinctive light of
comprehension and hope. This mysterious light does not do away with the
tragedy in people'
s lives or the tragic conflicts in peoples fundamental
attitudes that underlie their differences of opinions. It does, however,
enable people to transcend the conflict in being able to perceive it from a
different perspective and then, rather than judging it, to understand it in a
different light.
Two more respects in which Marcel'
s theater provides an
indispensable way of access to his philosophy merit highlighting. one
pertains to the distinctive dimension of human life that his thought
interrogates; the other relates to the unusual exigencies or high
expectations that Marcel held for those who would have dialogue with him.
Marcel expects his interlocutors to bring to the discussion a rich,
concrete experience of the subject under investigation. He also expects
them to become aware of alternate interpretations and to understand the
subjective attitudes from which these spring, and further expects that
anyone who performs a reflective clarification begins with an encounter
with the mystery in question. And, finally, he expects that anyone's
interpretation of a phenomenon will be derived from and confirmed
against an increasing awareness of the reality present within the
person'
s own life experience. He expects that one'
s grasp of the
authentic nature of a phenomenon and one'
s cognition of its requisite
17
conditions of possibility are gathered from the intense saturating
Présence of that reality as it touches and uplifts that person'
s life.(38)
In summary, Marcel expects anyone who philosophizes with him to be
constantly in touch with his or her own experience of the reality under
investigation, to interrogate it, to experience its features and its
essence in its various modes of "givenness," and then to develop and
verify ones rational interpretations against the presence of that
mystery within ones o w n life experience. Theater provides a first
original experience of this kind of thought as well as food to continually
nourish it.
Concrete dramatic approaches enhance ones experience of the
kind of reality Marcel'
s investigations explore. Marcel researches the
spiritual dimension of human life. This sacred dimension is accessible
primarily by way of inwardness and depth. Its nature and its condition of
possibility are best described in the language of subjectivity, which speaks
precisely in terms of how this kind of reality presents itself in the
conscious experience of incarnate persons.
On this matter, Martin Heidegger, a philosopher so different from
Gabriel Marcel in many other respects, agrees emphatically that
exploration of ones consciousness of the essential features of human
existence is the unique and indispensable pathway for discovering the
meaning of Being and the sense this gives to human life. In the
Préface to "The Invisible Threshold" Marcel affirms that his theater
concerns itself with questions of the human spirit. His works explore
people'
s experience of that sacred dimension of human existence, that
dimension of spirit that assures absolute worth to individual human
lives.(39)
Marcel'
s thought is concerned with human dignity. To examine
this kind of reality one has to encounter it where it occurs, that is,
precisely as it reveals itself to the conscious, affective, incarnate persons
whose life it affects. Marcel'
s philosophy deals with matters of the heart.
He treats these where they occur, namely within the privacy and depth
of a person's being. For it is only there, at the center of a person's
spiritual life, that the presence and nature of certain realities can come
to light and be acknowledged.(40)
Marcel explores, for example, how within someone's heart a decision is
formed that determines the orientation of that person's freedom and the
sense that person gives to his or her life. He explores how one
18
accedes to faith, how one struggles with unbelief. He describes how
one adopts an attitude of hope or falls prey to the gravitation toward
despair. He discloses how individuals influence and became part of one
another'
s lives. He looks at death and the alternate stances people adopt
toward it. He explores the possibility of genuine love and the tragedy of
its failure. He examines from within the ambiguity of the human
condition, and in the face of its tragedy he nevertheless discloses ways of
the heart for transcending any condemnation to absurdity or despair.
Marcel'
s theater shows these dramas of interiority. As characters
in the play live through their dramatic awakening, they communicate to
the audience something of what they are living and also something of
what they live by. As they come to a heightened consciousness of the
events affecting themselves, audiences can hear the echoes of this
dawning awareness occurring within their own lives.
Marcel's plays enable audiences to experience certain spiritual
realities through what he later called existential witness. He had
inquired, for himself first but then also for others, how the
transcendent, the sacred, or the spiritual dimension of individual lives
could become present to him in his unique subjectivity. He inquired as to
how, if individuals had not encountered certain spiritual realities directly,
they could come to experience then. Marcel recognized that as the lives
of others touch ours, we can encounter the transcendent spiritual reality
that is operative in these people’s lives.(41)
In this respect, Marcel'
s theater appears once again as a
privileged and indispensable way of access for entering into
philosophic reflection about these mysteries. Some people may have
significant experience and insight into these realities on their own.
Others may have less, very little, or almost none to speak of. Yet for all,
and especially in the case of those who would study and discuss some
of these topics together, Marcel'
s theater provides a rich and deepening
experience in which many can participate both personally and in
common with others.
Indeed, in the case of Marcel'
s work, theater provides a uniquely
valuable and a practically indispensable way of access to philosophic
reflection. This relationship is consistent with the metaphor of the three
concentric rings. If philosophy is conceived as a function of the theater,
then dramas can bring people to that place within themselves where
they encounter concretely the precise reality that needs to be present for
19
ones philosophic reflection to be experientially and realistically based.
Moreover, if philosophy, the outermost ring, is considered as an
outgrowth of music, then the reflective clarification that develops will not
only have intellectual rigor but it will also provide, like music, a deep
inward assurance of the Présence and meaningfulness of the reality
entertained.
All this is implied in Marcel'
s saying, so aptly yet so tersely, in the
essay "On the Ontological Mystery, that "it is in drama that metaphysics
occurs in concreto." (42)
Philosophy as the third and outermost ring of the three brings a
distinctive clarification to the articulation of Marcel'
s thought, even
though, as we continue to affirm, this clarification is most fully
appreciated when his philosophy is read in conjunction with his
dramatic presentations.
Philosophy
Philosophy, for Marcel, provides an accurate and explicit
articulation of questions in general terms. Philosophy then researches
and investigates these questions in a reflective and critically reasoned
manner. Philosophic analysis enables one to identify with clarity and
rigor, albeit in general terms, the nature of a particular phenomenon
that one has been investigating. Critically, philosophy lets one view
possible alternative interpretations and discern the subjective attitudes
and stances from which these various interpretations evolve. In this
manner, philosophy'
s critical reflection not only clarifies the essence of
what something is, but in bringing to light the various options and the
attitudes from which they spring, it enhances one's opportunity for
freedom in the response one makes toward the presence or absence of
that particular reality in ones own life.
Philosophy'
s contribution is distinctive and valuable. As Marcel
wrote in Presence and Immortality, philosophy brings to a level of
critically reasoned interpretation what was previously present only on
the levels of poetry and song.(43)
20
Concrete Approach
Gabriel Marcel distrusted abstractness. He even warned that a spirit
of abstraction is at the root of all fanaticism.(44) He insisted on the
importance of a concrete approach in philosophy. When he entertained
young people who were preparing for careers in the field of philosophy,
Marcel insisted that they formulate their ideas as one would if
addressing them to a person who was actually living the situation that
they wished to discuss. In the case of Marcel's thought, the need for
concrete approaches is not satisfied by simply offering an occasional
example as an illustration of a general principle. A concrete approach
involves adopting the perspectives of an inquirer whose life is caught
up in the issue under investigation, aware that the meaning and worth
of his or her life will be drastically affected by the results of ones
investigations. Marcel has affirmed that if individual people in their
concrete, incarnate lives are kept central to philosophic reflection one
encounters not only the uniqueness of those individuals, but also the
infinite depth and richness that are part of their lives.(45) Faithfulness
to the concrete approach of one who is, as it were, exploring and
charting the terrain of a particular mysterious dimension of human life
is of primary importance since the source and data for one'
s
interpretations should in fact be that mysterious, experiential dimension
of human life.(46) It is also important so that the yield of philosophic
reflection includes not merely perceiving the essence of something but
also encountering the concrete reality in its intense presence and full
saturation of givenness.(47) Marcel'
s philosophy is distinctive if not
unique, in that it not only provides for conceptual clarification, but also
strives for the Présence of the mysterious reality under investigation
as the data source for reflection and as a reality enriching the lives of
the questioners.
A Call to Be
There is an ethical dimension to Marcel'
s thought that is consistent
with its concrete approaches. Marcel expects that people will pose
questions about the meaning and value of human life with a view to
enhancing the quality of their own lives. So, as dramatic and
philosophic reflection clarify certain dimensions of human life, they do so
in such a way as to clarify the options and the various subjective
dispositions from which they spring. Thus Marcel'
s theater and
philosophy include a "call to be" that invites individuals in their
21
freedoms to respond and live authentically in the light of the values
they perceive.(48)
Neo-Socratic
Consistent with Marcel'
s concrete approaches, "neo-Socratic" is a
term he allowed as validly describing his approach to philosophy. The
style of his writing remains personal and conversational, and his
philosophic approach is intersubjective and dialogic. He guides
readers to investigate questions that arise within their own life
experience. Marcel continually invites readers to relate their reasoning
and reflection to "recollection" of their own lived experience. He guides
readers in reflections on varying and diverse experiences. Through a
process of interrogation leading to insight, developed from different
standpoints, Marcel leads his reader-interlocutor to perceive within his
or her own experience the essential features of the reality in question
and also the subjective or intersubjective conditions of possibility
requisite for its occurrence. Marcel, through his approach of interrogation
toward insight through intersubjective dialogue, intends, like Socrates, to
assist at the birth of true ideas and right understanding of the nature of
certain realities that can enhance the quality of one's life.
Phenomenological
Paul Ricoeur, who noted at Cerisy-La-Salle the dramatic
character of Marcel'
s thought, also stated that Marcel's mode of reflection
would be phenomenological even if Edmund Husserl had never
evolved a phenomenological method. (49) What Marcel describes as
"recollection" and "reflection" and what he performs as a concrete
experiential approach to the clarification of mystery does indeed follow
the pattern that the phenomenological method describes. l50) His
reflections appear so original in approach, so rich in content, and so
artful in execution, that one scarcely has the impression of a disciplined
technique being methodically applied. One has rather the impression of a
musical composition developed through artful improvisation. One has
only to read a masterful work like Marcel's essay "Sketch of a
Phenomenology and a Metaphysics of Hope," or, for that matter, “The
22
Mystery of Family" or "The Ego and its Relation to Others" to recognize
the positive brilliance and artful care with which he develops a
philosophic clarification of topics that concern him.(51) These essays
pursue their topic and develop smoothly as an interesting dialogue and
a rich, concrete, personal reflection. Yet, if one wishes to verify, one
finds that the various steps of phenomenological analysis have been
applied. The main interest of this is the verification it offers of the
critical rigor of Marcel'
s analyses. Yet the rigor is evident for most
readers from following the process of their own thinking, and the central
focus of the reader-interlocutor remains the vitality of the inquiry, the
richness of the clarification, and the depth of true and valuable insights.
Marcel'
s philosophic essays begin with a preliminary sketch of the reality in
question and an evocation of the questions it gives rise to. His approach is
consistently personal and experiential, reflecting on the mystery as
present in the concrete experience of the interrogators. The process of
reflective clarification views the reality from different standpoints and
interprets its essential features accurately. Various techniques of
entertaining alternate attitudes and interpretations are introduced as
part of the process of interrogation toward insight. This critical technique
serves not only to bring to light spurious or counterfeit approximations, but also
to sharpen and refine one's understanding of the genuine reality as
authentically lived. These essays lead to a recognition of the reality as
understood in its essential nature and its subjective conditions of possibility.
The mystery is present in the life experience of the investigator and this
entails a certain incitement to preserve its worth in our life situation.(52)
As the third and outermost ring of communication, philosophy makes a
definite contribution to the expression of Marcel's thought. Philosophy'
s
reflection and critical reasoning bring to expression in accurate and general
terms the questions and the insights previously present in his theater and
music only as poetry and song. The clarity and rigor that characterize
philosophic understanding bring one'
s consciousness to a new level of
explicitness. Philosophy'
s understanding also brings a new level of clarity to
the sense of uneasiness and inquiry awakened by the unanswered
questions of the plays. And philosophy brings a certain completeness to
the inquiry and research that theater brought to light and that music
foreshadowed. Thus the three concentric circles, music, theater, and
philosophy, bring to successive levels of awareness and critically
reflective consciousness the questions and the perspectives of light and
insight that are part of Marcel's life's work and thought.
23
Once the major part of Marcel'
s philosophy, drama, and musical
compositions were written, circa 1961 (the date of his last published play), it had
become evident to author and various commentators alike that there was a
fundamental unity in his life'
s work and an important complementarily to be
noted in different respects between his works of theater and philosophy.
PROPER RELATIONS BETWEEN THEATER AND PHILSOPHY
Various authors who have studied Marcel'
s writings have
illustrated the different ways his theater and philosophy can be
interrelated. Charles Moeller, a noted literary critic, sketched Marcel's
theme of hope, fleshing out this portrait with excerpts of dialogue from
several plays. In a more extensive study Marcel Belay, an outstanding
drama critic, examined the portrayal of death in fifteen of Marcel'
s
plays. Belay concluded this study with a final essay reflecting on the
significance of this theme in Marcel'
s thought. Gaston Fessard and
Joseph Chenu highlighted the substantial unity and essential
complementarity that exists between Marcel's theater and philosophy.
These noted scholars saw Marcel's thought developing as one route
traveled, with theater and philosophy representing the landscape
viewed on either side of the road or depicting either side of the same
height scaled. Fessard'
s work presented this idea principally in terms of
dramatic criticism. Chenu developed the idea and with very careful
balance showed the essential complementarily that exists between
Marcel's theater and philosophy and traced the progressive
development of various themes in Marcel'
s thought. Both these
authors brought into clear relief the prospective as well as the
concretizing role of theater relative to the philosophic thought.(53) Roger
Troisfontaines, Kenneth Gallagher, and Vincent Miceli, whose books are
classic introductions to Marcel'
s philosophy, present his theater as
integral to his thought. Each of these writers included in his book a
chapter or section developing this thesis. M. M. Davy, in her study of
Marcel'
s theater, identifies its distinctive qualities and highlights sore of
its traits and themes that are reflected in his philosophy. Paul Ricoeur,
an eminent philosopher, in a conference on Marcel'
s philosophy,
highlighted the essentially dramatic character of his thought, given his
dialogic approach and his essential concern for life as
intersubjective.(54)
24
As Marcel wrote in the Preface to (The Secret is in the Isles), the
way different authors interrelate his theater and philosophy and the
weight of importance these authors attach to one or the other will depend
largely on the preference and forte of the individual scholar.(55) This
remark seems to have been borne out by the facts in the past, and it
seems likely that it will be the case in the future as well.
However individuals may choose to interrelate Marcel's theater
and philosophy, they would be well advised to heed the directives and
information Marcel provides in his own writings. For Marcel the essential
relation between theater and philosophy is construed in terms of theater'
s
prospective and concretizing role. In Marcel'
s original inquiries, theater
was the first stage of research, with philosophy subsequent to it.
Early in his career, Marcel thought that theater alone might suffice
as his only form of literary expression. Soon, however, he realized that
both the theater and the philosophy were necessary. He began to
recognize that there was an essential complementarity, even a
substantial unity, between the two.(56)
Marcel recognized that theater and philosophy are distinct and
autonomous disciplines. Each has its own proper finality, and neither
should be made subservient to the other or to any other purpose. The
role of theater is to show life, not to teach or explain. The role of
philosophy is to reflect on questions and bring certain perspectives of
explanation to light in terms of rational discourse. So theater and
philosophy should remain as separate disciplines even though they
may have an essential complementarity.(57)
Always Prospective and Concretizing
In Marcel'
s writings reflecting on his theatrical and philosophical
works he always stressed that the essential complementarily between his
theater and his philosophy lay in the concretizing p r o s p e c t i v e role
of his theater. Marcel'
s theater is prospective as a first stage of inquiry
and exploration. Marcel observed that any question always occurred to
him first in terms of the dramatic conflict among p e o p l e in a concrete
situation. H e then watched the elements of conflict develop and play
themselves out in the lives of the characters of the play. Marcel's
dramatic imagination brought to the light of the theater certain conflicts and
fundamental antinomies that were part of his own life situation, and it
25
was thus that theater enabled him to envisage and confront some of the
fundamental questions affecting his own life. Marcel's theater also
played a concretizing role in that, in portraying the concrete situation of
the dramas, it enabled certain stances to be incarnated and various
attitudes to be voiced. This allowed certain questions and themes to
become clear in the light of the theater and find expression dramatically
long before Marcel ever conceived of any such notions philosophically
or become aware of their significance on the level of philosophic
discourse. In this fashion theater often anticipated and prepared the way
for what philosophy was to discover and reflect upon later.(58) A classic
instance of this is Abel'
s voicing the word "mystery" in the
denouement of (The Iconoclast), written in 1917-1921. The
philosophical significance of “mystery" was developed only much later,
appearing in the philosophical essay "On the Ontological Mystery"
published in 1933 in conjunction with the play The Broken World. (59)
On several occasions Marcel emphatically voiced that theater
anticipates philosophy, and the scholarly works of Fessard and Chenu
amply substantiate it.(60)
Paradox of Philosopher-Dramatist
In his later years Marcel reflected on the paradox he saw in the dual
vocation of philosopher-dramatist. For him, the paradox centered in
the fact that although his theater was concerned with fundamental
conflicts in the concrete situation of individual lives that gave rise to
questions and thus consciousness of ideas, his was in no way a
theater for ideas in any literal sense. Marcel'
s is not a theater that sets
out to illustrate a thesis. Nor does his theater propose to proselytize or
present propaganda for some ideology. It serves even less as a forum for
debate, presenting ideas in the form of reasoned argument. Therein
lies the paradox. This theater deals with ideas not philosophically, but
dramatically, as dawning in the consciousness of those whose lives are
caught up in the issues that give rise to questions about life'
s meaning
and worth.(61)
When most of Marcel'
s major works were complete it became
evident that there was an essential complementary, even a substantial
unity, between his theater and philosophy. These were described as
the landscape viewed on either side of the one road traveled. And, in
another homo viator metaphor, identified as alternate slopes of the
same height scaled. From the vantage point of a retrospective view one
26
can see progressively along the path of Marcel'
s life different questions
explored first dramatically and then philosophically. As he wrote in "An
Essay in Autobiography" it appeared to him as if his work is like that of
one who charts a territory that he had explored but which territory
each individual will want to explore on his or her own.(62)
Looking at Marcel'
s work as a whole, one can occasionally
consider some aspect of certain plays as illustrative of a philosophic
theme or insight. Yet even this risks reversing the dynamic of Marcel'
s
work and might lead to a misunderstanding or a misrepresentation of
Marcel'
s thought. This has occurred on occasion.(63) One is therefore
rightfully advised to respect the theater'
s concretizing and prospective
role as foremost to the relationship between Marcel'
s theater and his
philosophy.
It is hoped that reflection on Marcel'
s metaphor of three
concentric circles will serve as an attractive and enlightening introduction
to the nature of Marcel'
s thought. Reflection on the three circles
indicates what Marcel considers integral philosophic inquiry should
entail and emphasizes the essential complementarity that exists among
these three modes of communication. This same reflection should also
serve to highlight how and why theater opens up a uniquely valuable,
even indispensable, gateway to philosophic reflection.
A right understanding of Marcel'
s procedures for philosophic thinking
requires concrete approaches that awaken inward experience (as
music does), and initiate conscious personal reflection on a reality
directly and incarnately encountered (as theater does), so that one can,
in a manner that is both realistically based and critically reasoned
clarify, as philosophy does, the significance of its presence and/or
absence to evaluate the worth of one's life (as a person seeking freely
and responsibly to live an authentic human life does).
All three rings, each in its own way, bring us to a deep center
where we can encounter the presence of a mysterious reality within us,
a trans-subjective depth of the spiritual dimension of our lives. Music,
theater, and philosophy, each in its own way, enable us to clarify the
significance of this sacred dimension of humanity so that each of us may
live in its light, faithful to its call "to be" and responsive to its incitement "to
create."
27
Notes to Chapter One. An Introduction to Gabriel Marcel'
s Philosophic
Quest through Music and Theater
1. Gabriel Marcel, The Existential Background of Human Dignity,
The William James Lectures Delivered at Harvard University 1961-
62, Cambridge, MA., Harvard University Press, 1963, 178 pp. Gabriel
Marcel, The Mystery of Being, 2 volumes. The Gifford Lectures
Delivered at the University of Aberdeen, Scotland, translated by
G. S. Fraser. Vol. I, Reflection and Mystery, 270 pp., Vol. II, Faith
and Reality, 210 pp. First published, 1950 by the Harvill Press
Ltd., Great Britain. A Gateway Edition was published by Henry
Regnery Co. of Chicago, 1960. Reprinted by arrangement with
Regnery/Gateway by University Press of America, Lanham, MD.,
1982; St. Augustine’s Press, Notre Dame, IN, 200?.
2. Biographic data may be found in: Part Three, Section I, below,
pp. 177-183.
H.J. Blackham, Six Existentialist Thinkers, London, Routlege &
Kegan Paul, 1951.
I. M. Bochenski, Contemporary European Thought, Berkeley, CA.,
University of California Press, 1956.
Seymour Cain, Gabriel Marcel. New York, Hillary House, 1963;
South Bend, IN., H. Regnery/Gateway, 1979.
Kenneth T. Gallagher, The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, New York,
Fordham University Press, 1962, 1975.
Samuel Keen, Gabriel Marcel. Richmond, VA., John Knox Press,
1967.
Francis J. Lescoe, Existentialism with or without God, New York,
Alba House, 1974.
Vincent P. Miceli, Ascent to Being. Gabriel Marcel'
s Philosophy of
Communion, New York, Tournai, Paris, Rome, 1965.
David Roberts, Existentialism and Religious Belief, New York, Oxford
University Press, 1957.
28
Herbert Spiegelberg, The Phenomenological Movement, A Historical
Introduction, 2 Vols., The Hague, Martins Nijhoff, 1960.
29
Roger Troisfontaines, De L'Existence à l’Être. La Philosophie de
Gabriel Marcel, Louvain, Nauwelaerts; Paris, Vrin, 1952; 1965.
Gabriel Marcel, "An Essay in Autobiography," in The
Philosophy of Existentialism, Secaucus, NJ., The Citadel Press,
1956, pp. 104-28; En Chemin, vers quel éveil? Paris, Gallimard,
1971; "An Autobiographical Essay" (Spring 1969) in The
Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel (Library of Living Philosophers
Vol. XVII) ed. Paul A. Schilpp and Lewis E. Hahn, La Salle, IL.,
Open Court, 1984, pp. 3-68.
3. An allocution for the Alliance Française, "Le Paradoxe
du Philosophe--Dramaturge," Réalisations Sonores: Hughes De
Salle, Collection Française de Notre Temps Nous Confie, Sous
le patronage de L'
Alliance Française, présentation écrite sur la
pochette de Marc Blancpain. No date.
4. "Foreword" by Gabriel Marcel, pp. VII-X, March 26, 1962, to
Kenneth T. Gallagher'
s The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, New
York, Fordham University Press, 1962, 1975, p. VIII.
5. Commemorative medal commissioned by the National Mint
of France (L'
Hôtel Des Monnaies), Presence and Immortality,
Pittsburgh, PA., Duquesne University Press, 1967, pp. 7, 35; Ch.
Moeller, Littérature du XXe Siècle et Christianisme, Vol. IV,
Paris, Casterman, 1960, p. 129.
6. "Musique et littérature," Nouvelles littéraires, jeudi 17 juin
1948; Existential Background of Human Dignity, Cambridge,
MA., Harvard University Press, 1962, p. 21; En Chemin, vers
quel éveil?, Paris, Gallimard, 1971, p. 81; Louis Chaigne, Vie et
oeuvres d'
ecrivains, Vol. 4, Paris, F. Lanore, 1954, p. 193.
7. Préface à Le Seuil invisible, volume qui contient La Grâce
et Le Palais de Sable, Paris, Bernard Grasset, 1914, pp. 3, 8;
Preface to (The Invisible Threshold), an introduction to his first
two published plays, (Grace) and (The Sand Castle).
8. "An Essay in Autobiography," p. 127; "On the Ontological
Mystery,"
p. 18 in The Philosophy of Existentialism, Secaucus,
NJ, The Citadel press, 1956; The Mystery of Being, 2 vols., The
Gifford Lectures at University of Aberdeen, Scotland, Great
30
Britain, Harvill Press, 1950; Chicago, IL., Henry Regnery Co.,
Gateway Edition, 1960, vol. 1, p. 250, pp. 57-58; reprinted by
arrangement with Regnery/Gateway, Lanham, MD., University
Press of America, 1984.
The Philosophy of Existentialism contains "On the Ontological
Mystery," "Existence and Human Freedom," "'Testimony and
Existentialism," and "An Essay in Autobiography." The essay
"On the Ontological Mystery" was originally entitled "Position et
approches concretes du Mystère ontologique," a conference
presented at the Marseilles Society of Philosophy, January 21,
1933, and published in the same volume with Le Monde cassé
( The Broken World, ) Paris, Desclée de Brouwer, 1933. Etienne
Gilson remarked that this essay is as central to an
understanding of Gabriel Marcel'
s work as the Introduction to
Metaphysics is to Henri Bergson's.
9. "My Fundamental Purpose" (1937), pp. 13-30 in
Présence and Immortality, Pittsburgh, PA., Duquesne University
Press, 1967, p. 27. Original French version is "Mon Propos
fondamental," pp. 13-26 in Présence et Immortalité, Paris,
Flammarion, 1959, p. 24; The Drama of the Soul in Exile," A
lecture given by Gabriel Marcel in July 1950 to the Institut
Français in London, published as Préface to Gabriel Marcel:
Three Plays, A Man of God, Ariadne, The Votive Candle, trans.
with introduction by Richard Hayes, New York, Hill and Wang,
1965, p. 27.
10. Le Quartuor en fa dièze (The Quartet in F#), Paris,
Plon, 1925;
Mon Temps n’est pas le vôtre (My Time is Not Your Time),
Paris, Plon, 1955;
Le_Dard (The Sting), Paris, Plon, 1936;
Le Chemin de crête, Paris, Grasset, 1936, (Ariadne), in Three
Plays by Gabriel Marcel, New York, Hill and Wang, 1965.
Croissez et multipliez (Increase and Multiply), Paris, Plon, 1955.
The Unfathomable (March 1919, pp. 245-84 in Présence and
31
Immortality, Duquesne University Press, 1967; L'
Insondable, pp.
195-234 in Présence et Immortalité, Paris, Flammarion, 1959.
The Broken world, pp. 19-144 in The Existential Drama of Gabriel
Marcel, West Hartford, CT., St. Josephs College McAuley
Institute of Religious Studies, 1974; Le monde cassé, Paris,
Desclée de Brouwer, 1932.
Cf. - The Broken World, trans. & ed. Katharine Rose Hanley,
Milwaukee, Marquette University Press, 1998, pp..
La Grâce (Grace), pp. 9-209 in Le Seuil Invisible, Paris, Grasset,
1914.
Colombyre ou le brasier de la paix (Colombyre or the Torch of
Peace), pp. 8-155, Théâtre comique, Paris, Albin Michel,
1947.
11. "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," p. 30; "Les vrais problèmes de
Rome n’est plus dans Rome" (The actual problems of Rome is
no longer in Rome), in Rome n'
est plus dans Rome, Paris, La
Table Ronde, 1951, pp. 155-56; Existential Background of
Human Dignity, p. 106; Le Secret est dans les Iles, (The Secret is
in the Islands), Préface, Paris, Plon, 1967, p. 20; "An
Autobiographical Essay," (Spring 1969) in The Philosophy of
Gabriel Marcel, (The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. XVII) ed.
P. A. Schilpp and L. E. Hahn, La Salle, IL., Open Court, 1984, p.
60; En Chemin, vers quel éveil? Paris, Gallimard, 1971, pp. 235-
36.
12. Kenneth T. Gallagher, The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel,
Foreword by Gabriel Marcel, New York, Fordham University
Press, 1962, 1975, p. VIII.
13. Présence de Gabriel Marcel, Cahier 2-3, L'
Esthétique musicale
de Gabriel Marcel, Paris, Aubier, 1980, pp. 1-297; Louis Chaigne,
Vie et oeuvres d'
ecrivains, Vol. 4, Paris, F. Lanore, 1954, pp.
252-53. Cf. ff. Chronological Bibliography of Works by Gabriel
Marcel about his Theater, forty titles, pp. 39-42.
14. A Man of God, in Three Plays by Gabriel Marcel, New York, Hill
and Wang, 1965, pp. 35-114. Un Home de Dieu, Paris, Grasset,
1925; reedited, Paris, La Table Ronde, 1950. "La Lumière sur la
32
montagne," an unpublished play (1905) Marcel identified as a
childish version of the later work, A Man of God. The child'
s version
was, however, favorably reviewed by the critic and poet Fernand
Gregh. En Chemin, vers quel éveil?, p. 23. Gabriel Marcel'
s "An
Autobiographical Essay" (Spring 1969), pp. 16-17, published in The
Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, (The Library of Living Philosophers,
Vol. XVII), published in 1984, presents much information from En
Chemin, vers quel éveil? and makes it available for the first time
in English. Awakenings
15. Cf. ff. Chronological Bibliography of Works by Gabriel
Marcel about his Theater, pp. 39-42.
Three full-length books of drama criticism, Théâtre et Religion,
Paris, Vitte, 1958; L'
Heure Théâtrale, Paris, Plon, 1959; and
Regards sur le Théâtre de Claudel, Paris, Beauchesne,
1964.
Marcel'
s reviews as drama critic, working for over forty
years for Sept, Temps Présents, La Vie intellectuelle,
L'
Europe Nouvelle, and Nouvelles Littéraires, are by far too
numerous to list here. These reviews and others can be
located by using the excellent bibliographic sources listed in
Part Three, Section IV, below pp. 211 citing especially
the works of Roger Troisfontaines, 2 vols., De l'Existence à
l
'
être. La Philosophie de Gabriel Marcel Lettre Préface de
Gabriel Marcel, Louvain: Nauwelaerts; Paris: BeatriceNauwelaerts,
1953, 2e ed. 1968, vol. 2, Bibliographie de
Gabriel Marcel, pp. 381-464, in particular III. Articles de Les
Nouvelles Littéraires, pp. 427-42, IV. Journaux, Révues,
Avant-Propos, Divers, pp. 442-50, Conférences, pp. 450-
57, Notes, Entretiens, Débats, Présidences, Interviews, pp.
457-61; and the work of Francois H. Lapointe and Claire C.
Lapointe, Gabriel Marcel and His Critics, An International
Bibliography, (1928-1976), New York and London, Garland
Publishing, Inc., 1977, Part I, bibliography of Gabriel
Marcel'
s writings, pp. 7-107, arranged by years. Cf. also
Francois H. Lapointe, "The Writings of Gabriel Marcel,"
arranged by years, in The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel,
(The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. XVII), pp. 585-609,
ed. P. A. Schilpp and L. E. Hahn, La Salle, IL., Open Court,
1984.
33
16. "An Autobiographical Essay," p. 39; Cf. Part Three, Section I,
Biblio-biography, below, pp. 177-83.
17. Le Secret est dans les Iles (The Secret is in the Isles), Préface,
pp. 8-13, to the volume of three plays: Le Dard (The Sting,)
L'
Emissaire (The Emissary), and Le Signe de la Croix (The Sign of
the Cross), Paris, Plon, 1967, 349 pp.
18. Le Quatuor en fa dièze (The Quartet in F#); Le Coeur des autres
(The Rebellious Heart); L'
Insondable (The Unfathomable); Les
points sur les I (Dot the I); La Soif ou Les Coeurs avides (Thirst or
Eager Hearts); La Double Expertise (The Double Expertise); Le
Regard neuf (The New Look), among others treating struggles for
communication and love, and dealing with challenges to fidelity and
situations involving infidelity. Un Juste (A Just One); Le Dard (The
Sting); L'
Emissaire (The Emissary); Le Signe de la Croix (The
Sign of the Cross); Rome n’est plus dans Rome (Rome Is No
Longer in Rome); among others deal with political differences and
the struggle of individual conscience.
Mon Temps n’est pas le Vôtre (My Time is not Your Time)
portrays something deeper than the generation gap. Concern for
persons missing in action is portrayed in L'
Insondable (The
Unfathomable.) Fear of the menace of war is depicted in
Colombyre ou le brasier de la paix ( Colombyre or the Torch of
Peace ); and Rome n’est plus dans Rome (Rome Is No Longer in
Rome) conveys reactions to the menace of war. Le Quatuor en fa
dièze (The Quartet in F#), Le Coeur des autres (The Rebellious
Heart), Un Home de Dieu (A Man of God), Les points sur les I
(Dot the. I), Le Fanal (The Lantern), Le Chemin de Crête
(Ariadne), and others deal with struggles for success and
authenticity. La Grâce (Grace), Le Palais de Sable (The Sand
Castle), Les points sur les I (Dot the I), Le Fanal ( The Lantern ),
Le Dard, (The Sting), and others deal with faith. Music is a
principal theme in Le Quatuor en fa dièze (The Quartet in F#),
Mon Temps n’est pas le vôtre (My Time is not Your Time), and Le
Dard (The Sting). In Le Dard (The Sting), Le Coeur des autres
(The Rebellious Heart), Un Home de Dieu (A Man of God), and
Les points sur les'I (Dot the I) the quest for artistic, professional,
and personal integrity appears. Survival and life after death
appear in L'
Insondable (The Unfathomable), L'
Iconoclaste (The
34
Iconoclast), Le Fanal (The Lantern), L’ Horizon (The Horizon),
and Le Divertissement posthume (The Posthumous Joke).
19. The expression "what one lives by" or "what one lives on"
occurs often in Marcel'
s works in the sense that comes to light in the dialogue between Arnaud and Evelyne in La Soif, Act III, Scene
9, p. 445, and in "An Autobiographical Essay" (1969), in The
Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, (The Library of Living Philosophers,
Vol. XVII), ed. P. A. Schilpp and L. E. Hahn, La Salle, IL., Open
Court, 1984, p. 61.
20. Le Fanal, Paris, Armand Stock, 1936, Scenes 4, 6, and 7;
especially pp. 38-40. The Lantern, translated by Joseph
Cunneen and Elizabeth Stambler, in Cross Currents, Vol. VIII,
no. 2 (Spring 1958), pp. 129-43, Scenes 4, 6, and 7, especially pp.
136-37.
21. La Grâce (Grace), pp. 9-209, in Le Seuil Invisible, (The
Invisible Threshold), Paris, Bernard Grasset, 1914, pp. 202-
209. "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," p. 21.
22. "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," p. 27, L'
Heure
Théâtrale, p.vi.
23. Le Seuil Invisible, Paris, Bernard Grasset, 1914, p. 7; Le
Secret est dans les Iles, pp. 18-19; En Chemin vers quel éveil?,
Paris, Gallimard, 1973, p. 169.
24. The Drama of the Soul in Exile," p. 27; "Les vrais problèmes de
Rome n’est plus dans Rome," p. 162; "My Dramatic Works as
viewed by the Philosopher," p. 111-12; The Existential Background of
Human Dignity,_ pp. 5, 53, 107; "On the Ontological Mystery," pp.
26-27, in The Philosophy of Existentialism; The Philosophy of
Gabriel Marcel, (Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. XVII),
"Reply by Gabriel Marcel" to "The Idea of Mystery in the
Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel," pp. 272-73.
25. The Broken World, Act I, Scene 4, in The Existential Drama of
Gabriel Marcel, ed. Francis J. Lescoe, translated by Sr. J. M. P.
Colla, West Hartford, CT., McAuley Institute of Religious
Studies, 1974, p. 36.
35
26. "Introduction to the Theater of the Broken World," in The
Existential Drama of Gabriel Marcel, p. 10.
27. "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," pp. 27-28, 33.
28. The Rebellious Heart, Act III, Scene 3, in The Existential
Drama of Gabriel Marcel.
29. The Broken World, Act IV, Scene 7, pp. 141-44, especially pp.
143-44.
30. "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," pp. 28-29.
31. Ibid., pp. 30, 32-33; Le Secret est dans les Iles, p. 20; Préface,
in Percées vers un ailleurs, Paris, Fayard, 1973, p. l; "De la
recherche philosophique" in Entretiens autour de Gabriel Marcel,
Neuchâtel, à la Baconnière, 1976, p. 9.
32. L'
Heure théâtrale, De Giraudoux à Jean Paul Sartre, Paris, Pion,
1959, pp. III, IV; "My Dramatic Works as viewed by the Philosopher"
in Searchings, New York, Newman Press, 1967, translated from
the German Auf der Suche nach Wahrheit and Gerechtigkeit,
Verlag Knecht, 1964, a conference presented in Freiburg im
Bresgau, 1959, pp. 93-118, especially pp. 108, 117.
33. Marcel Belay, in the discussion of "Gabriel Marcel et la
Phénoméenolgie" presentation by Paul Ricoeur in Entretiens
autour de Gabriel Marcel, p. 88.
34. "De la recherche philosophique," pp. 9-10, 16-17, in Entretiens
autour de Gabriel Marcel; Existential Background of Human
Dignity, William James Lectures delivered at Harvard University,
Cartridge, MA., Harvard University Press, 1963, p. 93; Le Secret
est dans les Iles, p. 12; En Chemin, vers quel éveil? Paris,
Gallimard, 1971, pp. 233-34.
35. Gaston Fessard, "'Théâtre et Mystère," published as an
introductory essay to La Soif, Paris, Desclée de Brouwer, 1938,
pp. 5-116; Notes de 1 auteur: La Chapelle Ardente, in Trois
Pièces, Paris, Plan, 1931, p. 142; "The Drama of the Soul in
Exile," pp. 15, 21-22, 30, 32.
36
36. Notes de l'
auteur: La Chapelle Ardente, p. 142; "The Drama of
the Soul in Exile," pp. 17, 21, 22, 30, 33.
37. "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," pp. 21, 22-23; "My
Dramatic Works as viewed by the Philosopher," p. 115;
L’Heure Théâtrale, p. VII.
38. "Sketch of a Phenomenology and a Metaphysics of Hope," pp.
29-67 in Homo Viator, New York, Harper and Bros., 1962, p.
29. Earlier edition, H. Regnery, Chicago, 1951.
39. Préface, La Seuil Invisible (The Invisible Threshold), p. 8. This is
also the lead argument of The Existential Background of Human
Dignity.
40. "On the Ontological Mystery," pp. 17-22, esp. p. 22; The
Existential Background of Human Dignity, p. 53; Reply by Gabriel
Marcel to "The Idea of Mystery in the Philosophy of Gabriel
Marcel," in The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, (Library of Living
Philosophers, Vol. XVII), p. 272.
41. Grâce, in Le Seuil Invisible, pp. 207-209, esp. p. 209; Les points
sur les I, in Théâtre comique, Paris, Albin Michel, 1947, pp. 142-
44; Dot the I, translated by K. R. Hanley, in Two One Act Plays
by Gabriel Marcel, Lanham, MD., University Press of America,
pp. l-21; "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," pp. 22, 27; La Soif (The
Thirst), Paris, Desclée de Brouwer, 1938; reedited Les Coeurs
avides, (Eager Hearts), Paris, La Table Ronde, 1952; later
published La Soif ou Les Coeurs avides in Cinq Pieces Majeures:
Un Homme de Dieu, Le Monde cassé, Le Chemin de crête, La
Soif, and Le Signe de la Croix, Paris, Plon, 1973, pp. 357-450, act
3, scene 9, p. 445; The Drama of the Soul in Exile, pp. 22, 27;
The Existential Background of Human Dignity, pp. 63, 79, 92.
42. "I am convinced that it is in drama and through drama that
metaphysical thought grasps and defines itself in concreto," "On the
Ontological Mystery" in The Philosophy of Existentialism, p. 26.
43. "Presence and Immortality" (1951) pp. 229-44, in Présence and
Immortality, Pittsburgh, PA., Duquesne University Press, 1967, p.
232. "Présence et immortalité," (1951) pp. 179-93 in Présence et
37
immortalité, Paris, Flammarion, 1959, p. 183.
44. Foreword to Kenneth Gallagher'
s The Philosophy of Gabriel
Marcel, p. VIII; Postface, Rome n’est plus dans Rome, p. 160; The
Existential Background of Human Dignity, p. 123; Gabriel Marcel s
replies passim in The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, (Library of
Living Philosophers Vol. XVII); Allocution for the Alliance
Française, "Gabriel Marcel: Le Paradoxe du Philosophe--
Dramaturge."
45. "My Fundamental Purpose" (1937), pp. 13-30 in Presence and
Immortality, p. 29; "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," p. 27.
46. "An Essay in Autobiography," pp. 104-28 in The Philosophy of
Existentialism; The Mystery of Being, 2 vols; "The Drama of the
Soul in Exile," pp. 27-28; The Existential Background of Human
Dignity, p. 50.
47. "Sketch of a Phenomenology and a Metaphysics of Hope," pp.
29-67 in Homo Viator, p. 29. "This experience, which is that of '
I
hope..., must, like the fundamental experience of faith, '
I believe...,"
be purified; or, more exactly, we must pass from this experience in
its diluted or diffused state to the same experience, touched--I do not
say absolutely conceived--at its highest tension or again at its point
of complete saturation."
48. "Les valeurs spirituelles dans le théâtre français contemporian,"
Orientations réligieuses, intellectuelles et littéraires, June 25, 1937,
Belgium, pp. 768-98, p. 789; cited by Gaston Fessard in "Théâtre
et Mystere," p. 53; "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," pp. 33-34;
L’Heure Théâtrale, pp. VII-VIII.
49. Paul Ricoeur, "Gabriel Marcel et la Phénoménologie," pp. 53-74,
discussion pp. 75-94, in Entretiens autour de Gabriel Marcel, at
Cerisy la Salle, August 1973; "Gabriel Marcel and
Phenomenology" in The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, (Library of
Living Philosophers Vol. XVII), pp. 471-94. Reply by Gabriel
Marcel, pp. 495-98.
50. "On the Ontological Mystery", pp. 23-26; The Existential
Background of Human Dignity, p. 88.
38
51. Homo Viator Introduction to a Metaphysic of Hope, translated by
Erma Craufurd, New York, Harper and Bros., Harper Torchbooks
(The Cloister Library), 1962; originally published in English by
Victor Gollancz, Ltd., London, and Henry Refinery Company,
Chicago, in 1951; reprinted in 1962 by arrangements with Editions
Montaigne. "Sketch of a Phenomenology and a Metaphysic of
Hope," pp. 29-67; "The Mystery of Family," pp. 68-97; “The Ego
and its Relation to Others," pp. 13-28.
52. "Pour un renouveau de la spiritualité dans l'
art dramatique,"
Combat, February, 1937, cited by Gaston Fessard in "Théâtre et
Mystère," p. 70; L'
Heure Théâtrale, pp. VII-VIII.
53. Charles Moeller, "Gabriel Marcel et le mystère'
de
l
'
espérance," pp. 149-279 in Littérature du XXe siècle et
christianisme, IV. L'
Espérance en Dieu notre père. Paris,
Casterman, 1960.
Marcel Belay, La Mort dans le théâtre de Gabriel Marcel, Paris,
Vrin, 1980,
Gaston Fessard, Théâtre et mystère. Introduction à Gabriel
Marcel, Paris, Tequi, 1938.
Zachary Taylor Ralston, Gabriel Marcel'
s Paradoxical
Expression of Mystery: A Stylistic Study of "La Soif,"
Washington, D.C., The Catholic University of America Press,
1961.
Joseph Chenu, Le Théâtre de Gabriel Marcel et sa signification
métaphysique, Paris, Aubier, 1948.
Guillemine de Lacoste, "The Notion of Participation in the Early
Drama and Early Journals of Gabriel Marcel," Philosophy
Today, Vol. 19, (Spring 1975), pp. 50-60.
54. Roger Troisfontaines, De l'
existence a l’être. La Philosophie de
Gabriel Marcel. 2 vols. Louvain, Nauwelaerts; Paris, Beatrice
Nauwelaerts et J. Vrin, 1953; 2nd ed., 1968. Préface by Gabriel
Marcel. Bibliography.
39
Kenneth T. Gallagher, The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel.
Foreword by Gabriel Marcel. New York, Fordham University Press,
1962; 1975.
Vincent P. Miceli, Ascent to Being: Gabriel Marcel'
s Philosophy
of Communion, Foreword by Gabriel Marcel. Paris, Desclée de
Brouwer, 1965.
Louis Chaigne, Vie et œuvres d’ écrivains, IV, Paris, F. Lanore,
1954.
Marie-Madeleine Davy, Un Philosophe itinérant. Gabriel Marcel:
Paris, Flammarion, 1959.
Paul Ricoeur, Gabriel Marcel et Karl Jaspers, deux maîtres de
l
'
Existentialisme, Paris, Editions du Temps Présent, 1948; and
Entretiens Paul Ricoeur, Gabriel Marcel, Paris, 1968, translated
by Peter MCormick as "Conversations between Paul Ricoeur and
Gabriel Marcel" in Tragic Wisdom and Beyond, Evanston, IL.,
Northwestern University Press,1973; and “Gabriel Marcel et la
Phénoménologie" in Entretiens autour de Gabriel Marcel,
Neuchâtel, à la Baconnière, 1976; "Gabriel Marcel and
Phenomenology" in The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel (Library
of Living Philosophers Vol. XVII) ed. P. A. Schilpp and L. E. Hahn,
La Salle, IL., Open Court, 1984.
Simonne Plourde, Gabriel Marcel. Philosophe et témoin de
l’espérance. Montréal, Les Presses de l’ Université du Quebec,
1975.
55. Préface to Le Secret est dans les Iles, pp. 7-8.
56. Le Monde cassé: Avant-Propos cited by G. Fessard in "Théâtre
et Mystère," p. 9; Gaston Fessard, "Théâtre et Mystère,"
pp. 7-9;
"My Dramatic Works as Viewed by the Philosopher," pp. 115-18;
"Introduction," pp. 7-13 in Paix sur la terre, Deux discours une
Tragédie, Paris, Aubier, 1965; The Existential Background of
Human Dignity, p. 62; "
An Autobiographical Essay," p. 58; En
Chemin, vers quel éveil?, p. 139; Reply by Gabriel Marcel to "The
Idea of Mystery in the Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel," in The
Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, p. 273; Allocution for the Alliance
Française, Gabriel Marcel: Le Paradoxe du Philosophe-
40
Dramaturge.
57. "My Dramatic Works as Viewed by the Philosopher," p. 106.
58. "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," pp. 29-30; Notes d'
Auteur:
Chapelle Ardente, (1950), D. 142; "My Dramatic Works as Viewed
by the Philosopher," pp. 115-16; The Existential Background of
Human Dignity, p. 62, pp. 13-14; Préface to Percées vers un
ailleurs, pp. II-VII.
59. L'Iconoclaste, Pièce en quatre actes, Collection Nouvelle de la
France dramatique. (Répertoire choisi du Théâtre moderne), No.
13 Supplement to the Revue Hebdomadaire January 27, 1923,
Paris, Librairie Stock; Being and Having, pp. 116-20, 111, 141,
101; "On the Ontological Mystery," pp. 19-23; Creative Fidelity, p.
68; "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," pp. 28-30; The Existential
Background of Human Dignity, pp. 48, 50-53.
60. Gaston Fessard, "Théâtre et Mystère," pp. 7-9; Joseph Chenu, Le
Théâtre de Gabriel Marcel et sa signification métaphysique, pp.
17-18; Part Three, Section II, below pp. 187-96.
61. "Préface," Le Seuil Invisible, pp. 4-8; "My Dramatic Works as
viewed by the Philosopher," p. 102.
62. " A n Essay in Autobiography," p. 128; "The Drama of the Soul in
Exile," pp. 38, 27-28; The Existential Background of Human
Dignity, p. 50.
63. "My Dramatic Works as viewed by the Philosopher," pp. 108-
109.
41
Chronological Bibliography Of Works By Gabriel Marcel About His Theater
1. "Préface," Le Seuil Invisible, Paris: Editions Grasset, 1914, pp. l8.
2. "Réflexions sur le Tragique," L'
Essor, No. 13, December 1921.
3. "Remarques sur l’Iconoclaste," Revue Hebdomadalre, 27
January 1923, pp. 492-500.
4. "Tragique et Personnalité," Nouvelle Revue Française,
January 1924, pp. 37-45.
5. "Notes sur évaluation tragique," Journal de Psychologie, JanuaryMarch
1926, pp. 68-76.
6. "
L’avant propos," Le Monde cassé," Paris: Desclée de
Brouwer, 1933, pp. 7-9.
7. "Position et approches concrètes du Mystère ontologique,"
Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1933, essay published with Le
monde cassé.
8. "Influence du Théâtre," Revue des Jeunes, 5 March 1935, pp.
349-62.
9. "Pour un renouveau de la spiritualité dans l'art
dramatique," Combat, February 1937, pp. 458-68.
10. "Réflexions sur les exigences d’un Théâtre chrétien," Vie
Intellectuelle, 25 March 1937, pp. 458-68.
11. "Les Valeurs spirituelles dans le Théâtre français contemporain,"
Orientations religiousness, intellectuelles et littéraires, Belgium: 25
June 1937, pp. 768-96.
12. "Postface" de L’Horizon, written 1944, reissued in
Percées vers un ailleurs, Paris: Fayard, 1973, pp. 367-78.
13. "Le Témoignage come localisation de l’existential," La Nouvelle
Revue Théologique, 78th year, t. 68, no. 2, March-April 1946,
42
pp. 182-91.
14. "De l‘
Audace en métaphysique," (1947), Revue de
Métaphysique et de Morale, reissued in Percées vers un
ailleurs, Paris: Fayard, 1973.
15. "Note de l'auteur," La Chapelle Ardente, Paris: La Table
Ronde, 1950, pp. 139-42.
16. "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," Lecture given July 1950 at
l’Institut Françeis in London, Preface, Three Plays, London:
Seeker and Warburg, 1952; New York: Hill and Wang, 1958,
1965, pp. 13-34.
17. "Les vrais problèmes de Rome n’est plus dans Rome,"
Conférence 18 May 1951; Postface, Rome n'
est plus
dans Rome, Paris: La Table Ronde, 1951, pp. 149-78.
18. "'Théâtre et Philosophie. Leurs rapports dans mon
oeuvre," in Le Théâtre contemporain (Recherches et
Débats, no. 2), Paris: A. Fayard, 1952, pp. 17-42.
19. "
Postface," Mon Temps n'est pas le votre, Paris: Plon,
1955, pp. 237-48.
20. "Postface," Croissez et multipliez, Paris: Plon, 1955, pp.
201-13.
21. "L'atheisme philosophique et la dialectique de la
conscience réligieuse," Athéisme contemporain, (Croire,
penser, espérer). Genève: Labor et Fides; Paris: Librairie
Protestante, 1956, p. 107.
22. Théâtre et Religion, Paris: Vitte, 1958: "Religion et
Blasphème dans le Théâtre français contemporain,"
Conference at Brussels, 1956, pp. 9-52; "L'idée du drame
chrétien dans son rapport au Théâtre actuel," Conference
at Cobourg in Germany, 1957, pp. 53-97.
23. "
Postface,"
La Dimension Florestan, Paris: Plon, 1958,
pp. 159-69.
43
24. "Le Crépuscule du sens commun," essay published with
La Dimension Florestan, Paris: Plon, 1958, pp. 170-212.
25. "My Dramatic Works as Viewed by the Philosopher,"
Conference at Freiburg im Breisgau, 1959; Searchings, New
York: Newman Press, 1967, pp. 93-118.
26. "Avant-Propos," Présence et lmmortalité, Paris: Flamarion,
1959, pp. 7-9; "Author's Préface," Presence and Immortality,
translated by Michael A. Machado and revised by Henry J.
Koren, Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1967, pp. 7-
10.
27. "Avant-Propos," L'
Heure théâtrale, Paris: Plan, 1959, pp. iii-xiii.
28. The Existential Background of Human Dignity, The William James
Lectures delivered at Harvard University 1961-62, Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1963, 178 pp.
29. "Foreword" dated March 1962 to Kenneth T. Gallagher'
s The
Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, New York: Fordham University Press,
1962; reissued 1975, pp. VII-X.
30. Regards sur le Théâtre de Claudel, Paris: Beauchesne, 1964, 175
pp.
31. "Foreword" to Vincent P. Miceli, S. J.'
s Ascent to Being: Gabriel
Marcel'
s Philosophy of Communion, Paris, New York, Tournai,
Rome: Desclée Company, 1965, pp. IX-XI.
32. "Avant-Propos," Paix sur la Terre, Paris: Aubier, 1965, pp. 7-13.
33. "Préface," Le Secret est dans les Iles, Paris: Plon, 1967, pp. 7-
24.
34. En chemin vers quel eveil? Paris: Gallimard, 1971, 301 PP.
35. "Note sur l'
attestation créatrice dans mon oeuvre," Archivo di
Filosofia, 1972, pp. 531-34.
36. "Préface," Percées vers un ailleurs, Paris: Fayard, 1973, pp. IX.
44
37. "Introduction," The Existential Drama of Gabriel Marcel, West
Hartford, CT: McAuley Institute of Religious Studies Press, 1974;
letter to Francis J. Lescoe, editor, dated February l, 1973, pp. 6-8,
introduction enclosed pp. 9-18.
38. "De la recherche philosophique," Entretiens autour de Gabriel
Marcel at Cerisy-la-Salle 24-31 August 1973, Neuchatel,
Switzerland, Editions de la Baconniere, 1976, pp. 9-19.
39. "Le Paradoxe du Philosophe - Dramaturge," Réalisations
Sonores: Hughes De Salle, Collection Française de Notre
Temps Nous Confie, Sous le patronage de l‘
Alliance
Française, présentation écrite sur la pochette de Marc
Blancpain, no date.
40. "An Autobiographical Essay" (Spring 1969), and replies to essays in
The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, The Library of Living
Philosophers, Vol. XVII, Paul A. Schilpp and Lends E. Hahn,
editors, La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1984, pp. l-68, et passim.
45
Bibliography Of Works On Gabriel Marcel That Clarify The Nature Of His
Theater And Its Relationship To His Philosophy
Archambault, Paul. "Gabriel Marcel," in Témoins du spiritual, Paris:
Bloud & Gay, 1933, pp. 139-76; Colin, 1947.
Bagot, Jean-Pierre. Connaissance et amour. Essai sur la
philosophie de Gabriel Marcel. Paris: Beauchesne et ses fils,
1958.
Belanger, Gerard. L'
Amour, chemin de la liberté. Paris: Editions
ouvrières, 1965.
Belay, Marcel. "
Commentaire sur l’Horizon," in Percées vers un
ailleurs, Paris: Fayard, 1973, pp. 379-404.
____. "Commentaire sur l’Iconoclaste," in Percées vers un ailleurs,
Paris: Fayard, 1973, pp. 169-97.
____. "Etude sur Le Mort de Demain,"
in Entretiens autour de Gabriel
Marcel, Neuchâtel: à La Baconnière, 1976, pp. 131-38.
____. "La Grace dans Le Monde cassé" (Entretiens de Dijon de Mars
1973), Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, July-September
1974, 79th year, no. 3, pp. 370-75; discussion pp. 376-82.
____. "La Mort et les morts dans l’oeuvre théâtrale de Gabriel
Marcel." Doctoral dissertation, University of Dijon, France,
1977.
_____. La Mort dans le Théâtre de Gabriel Marcel, Paris: Vrin,
1980.
Berger, Gaston. "Constitution de l’
univers théâtral," in Mélanges
Georges Jamati. Paris: Editions du Centre National de la
Recherche Scientifique, Paris, 1956.
Bernard, Michel. La philosophie réligieuse de Gabriel Marcel. Etude
critique. Le Puy: Cahiers du Nouvel Humanisme, 1952.
46
Berning, Vincent. "Données et conditions de l'
accueil fait en Allemagne
à Gabriel Marcel, philosophe et dramaturge," pp. 211-19,
discussion pp. 220-37 in Entretiens autour de Gabriel Marcel,
Neuchâtel: à la Baconnière, 1976.
Boutang, Pierre. Gabriel Marcel interrogé par Pierre Boutanq, followed
by "Position et approches concrètes du Mystère ontologique."
Paris: J. M. Place, (Archives du XXe Siecle), 1977, pp. 7-114.
____ . "Le Souci de la Transcendence," Revue de Métaphysique et de
Morale, Vol. 79, No. 3, (July-Sept. 1974), pp. 315-37.
____ . La terreur en question. Lettre à Gabriel Marcel. Paris:
Fasquelles Editeurs, 1958.
Bugbee, Henry G. "L'
exigence ontologique" in The Philosophy of Gabriel
Marcel. Vol. XVII (The Library of Living Philosophers) ed. P. A.
Schilpp and L. E. Hahn, La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1984, pp. 81-93,
reply pp. 94-98.
Cain, Seymour. Gabriel Marcel. New York: Hillary House, 1963; London:
Bower and Bower, 1963; South Bend, IN: Regnery/Gateway,
Inc., 1979.
Chaigne, Louis. Vie et oeuvres d '
écrivains. 4ième série. Paris: Lanore,
1954.
Chastaing, Maxine. "Le langage théâtral de Gabriel Marcel," (Entretiens
de Dijon de mars 1973), Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, Vol.
79, No. 3 (July-September 1974), pp. 354-63; discussion pp. 364-
66.
Cheetham, M. "L'
actualité de Monde cassé de Gabriel
Marcel,"(Entretiens de Dijon de mars 1973), Revue de
Métaphysique et de Morale, Vol. 79, No. 3 (July-September 1974),
pp. 367-69.
Chenu, Joseph. Le Théâtre de Gabriel Marcel et sa
signification métaphysique, Paris: Aubier, 1948.
____. "Théâtre et Métaphysique," pp. 115-22, discussion, pp.
123-30 in Entretiens autour de Gabriel Marcel,
47
Neuchâtel: à la Baconnière, 1976.
Davy, Marie-Madeleine. Un philosophe itinérant. Gabriel Marcel,
Paris: Flammarion, 1959.
De Corte, Marcel. La philosophie de Gabriel Marcel, Paris: Tequi,
1938.
Delhomme Jeanne. "Un Homme Dieu," La Table Ronde, No. 24
(December 1949), pp. 48-52.
____."Témoignage et dialectique," pp. 117-201, in Existentialisme
chrétien Gabriel Marcel, Paris: Plon, 1947.
Dubois-Dumée, J. P. "Solitude et communion dans le Théâtre de Gabriel
Marcel," pp. 249-90, in Existentialisme chrétien: Gabriel Marcel,
Paris : Plon, 1947.
De Lacoste, Guillemine. "Man'
s Creativity in the Thought of
Marcel," New Scolasticism, 48 (Autumn 1974), pp. 409-23.
____. "
The Notion of Participation in the Early Drama and Early
Journals of Gabriel Marcel," Philosophy Today, Vol. 19
(Spring 1975), pp. 50-60.
Fessard, Gaston. Théâtre et Mystère, Paris: Tequi, 1938.
____."Théâtre et Mystère. Le sens de l’oeuvre dramatique de Gabriel
Marcel," Etudes, No. 234 (1938), pp. 738-60; and Ibid., No. 235
(1938), pp. 40-60.
____. "Théâtre et Mystère." Préface to La Soif by Gabriel Marcel, Paris:
Desclée de Brouwer, 1938.
Gallagher, Kenneth T. The Philosophy_of_Gabriel_Marcel, Foreword by
Gabriel Marcel, New York: Fordham University Press, 1962 and
1975.
____ . "Truth and Freedom in Marcel," The Philosophy of Gabriel
Marcel. (The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. XVII) ed P. A.
Schillp and L. E. Hahn, La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1984, pp. 371-
88, reply pp. 389-90.
48
Gilson, Etienne. Existentialisme chrétien: Gabriel Marcel.
Présentation by Etienne Gilson. Text by Jeanne Delhomme, Roger
Troisfontaines, Pierre Colin, J. P. Dubois-Dumee, Gabriel
Marcel, Paris: Plon, 1947.
____."A unique philosopher," Philsophy_Today vol. 3 (Winter
1959), pp. 278-89.
Gouhier, Henri. L’Essence du Théâtre. ( Essais et Critiques, 4) Paris: Plon;
Brussels: de Klogge, 1943; new edition, Paris: Aubier, 1968.
_____."Le Théâtre dans la pensée de Gabriel Marcel," in Savoir, faire,
espérer: limites de la_raison, 2 volumes published on the occasion
of the fiftieth anniversary of the School of Philosophie and Religious
Sciences and in honor of Msgr. Henri Van Camp. Brussels:
Publications des Facultés Universitaires Saint L o u i s , 1976, pp.
407-23.
____.Le Théâtre et existence (Philosophie de l'esprit), Paris: Aubier,
1952; reissued J. Vrin, 1973.
____ ."Théâtre et engagement" in Entretiens autour de Gabriel
Marcel, Neuchâtel: à la Baconnière, 1976, pp. 95-102,
discussion pp. 103-13.
____ .L Oeuvre théâtrale (Bibliothèque d'
Esthétique), Paris:
Flammarion, 1958.
____."Ou en sommes nous?" Recherches et Débats Théâtre
Contemporain, Paris: Fayard, 1952, pp. 9-16.
____."Philosophie et Théâtre" dans L ’ E n c y c l o p é d i e française,
t.XIX, Philosohie Religion, Paris: Larousse, 1957, 19. 30 6-8.
____."Tragique et Transcendence" in Le Théâtre tragique, Etudes
réunies et présentées par Jean Jacquot, Paris, Centre National de
la Recherche scientifique, 3rd edition 1970, pp. 479-83.
49
Hartshorne, Charles. "Marcel on God and Causality," The
Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, (The Library of Living
Philosophers Vol. XVII) ed. P. A. Schilpp and L. E. Hahn, La Salle,
IL: Open Court, 1984, pp. 353-66, reply by Gabriel Marcel, pp.
367-70.
Hocking, W. E. "Marcel and the Ground Issues of Metaphysics,"
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (1954), pp. 439-69.
Keen, Samuel. "The Development of the Idea of Being in the Thought
of Marcel," The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel (Library of Living
Philosophers Vol_ XVII), ed. P. A. Schilpp and L. E. Hahn, La
Salle, IL: Open Court, 1984, pp. 99-120, reply by Gabriel Marcel
pp. 121-22.
____. Gabriel Marcel, London: Carey Kingsgate Press, 1967;
Richmond, VA: John Knox Press, 1967.
Jouve, Raymond. "Un Théâtre de la Sincereté, Gabriel Marcel,
métaphysicien et dramaturge," Etudes, 5 and 20 April 1932, pp. 21-
34; 171-84.
Lescoe, Francis J. Existentialism with or without God, New York: Alba
House, 1974, Chapter III, pp 77-132.
____.(ed.) The Existentialist Drama of Gabriel Marcel, Letter and
Introduction by Gabriel Marcel. Introduction by Francis J.
Lescoe. The Broken World and The Rebellious Heart, English
versions of Le Monde cassé and Le Coeur des autres, translated
by Sister J. Marita Paul Colla, R. S. M., and Rev. Francis C.
O'
Hara, respectively, West Hartford, CT: McAuley Institute, St.
Joseph College, 1974.
Miceli, Vincent P. Ascent_to Being, Gabriel Marcel's Philosophy of
Communion, New York, Tournai, Paris, Rome: Desclée, 1965.
Moeller, Charles. "Gabriel Marcel et le mystère de
l’espérance," pp. 149-79, in Littératue du XXe siècle et
christianisme, IV, Es p é r a n c e en Dieu notre Père,
Paris: Casterman, 1960.
Man and Salvation in Literature, translated by Charles Underhill Quinn,
50
Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1970.
Mesnard, Pierre. "Le Monde cassé" in La Vie Intellectuelle, 15 March
1935, pp. 306-12.
Ngimbi-Nseka, H. Tragigue et Intersubjectivité dans la Philosophie d e
Gabriel Marcel, Mayidi, B. P. 6/224. Inkisi: Publications du Grand
Seminaire de Mayidi No. 1, 1981.
Novak, Michael. "Marcel at Harvard," The Commonweal, Vol. 77, No. 2,
(Oct. 5, 1962), pp. 31-33.
O'
Malley, John B. The Fellowship of Being, An essay on the concept of
person in the philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, The Hague: Martinus
Nijhoff, 1966.
Parain-Vial, Jeanne. Gabriel Marcel et les niveaux de
l’expérience Présentation, choix de textes et textes
inédites, Paris: Seghers, 1966.
____ . "L'
Être et essences dans la philosophie de Gabriel Marcel,"
Revue de Théologie et de P h i l o s o p h i e , No. 2(1974),
PP. 81-98.
____."L'
Être et le Temps chez Gabriel Marcel," pp. 187-201;
discussion pp. 202-10, in Entretiens autour de Gabriel
Marcel, Neuchâtel: à la Baconnière, 1976.
____."L'
espérance et l’être dans la philosophie de Gabriel Marcel," Les
Etudes philosophiques, January-March 1975, pp. 19-30.
____."Sur la paternité selon Gabriel Marcel," Archives de
Philosophie du Droit, Tome 20, (1975), pp. 149-62.
____ . "Le Tragique: L'
expérience existentielle face à la
contestation marxiste," Revue de Métaphysique et de
Morale, pp. 246-60.
Pax, Clyde Victor. An Existentialist Approach to God: A Study of Gabriel
Marcel, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1972.
____."Marcel’s Way of Creative Fidelity," Philosophy Today, Vol. 19
51
(Spring 1975), pp. 12-21.
Piguet, J. Claude. "De l'
esthétique à la métaphysique," Revue
de Théologie et de Philosophie Vol. 8, no. l, 1958, pp. 30-
41.
Plourde, Simonne. Gabriel Marcel philosophe et temoin de
l
'
espérance, Montréal: Les Presses de l'
Université de Quebec,
1975.
____. Jeanne Parain-Vial, Rene Davignon, Marcel Belay.
Vocabulaire philosophique de Gabriel Marcel, (Recherches.
Nouvelle Serie - 6) Montreal, Bellarmin, Paris, Cerf, 1985, p.
241.
Prini, Pietro. Gabriel Marcel la metodología dell’inverificabile, Pref. di
Gabriel Marcel, Roma: Studium, 1950. 125 pp. French trans.
Gabriel Marcel et la méthodologie de l inverifiable, Lettre-Préface
de Gabriel Marcel, Paris, Desclée de Brouwer, 1952, 129 pp. (2nd
ed. Roma: Studium Abete, 1968, 170 pp.).
____ ."A Methodology of the Unverifiable," The Philosophy of Gabriel
Marcel, (The Library of Living Philosophers Vol. XVII), ed. P. A.
Schilpp and L, E. Hahn, La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1984, pp. 205-39;
Reply by Gabriel Marcel, pp. 240-43.
Ralston, Zachary Taylor. Gabriel Marcel'
s Paradoxical Expression of
Mystery, A Stylistic Study of Ia Soif, Washington, D.C.: The Catholic
University of America Press, 1961.
Ricoeur, Paul. Entretiens Paul Ricour, Gabriel Marcel, Paris: Aubier,
Montaigne, 1968.
____. "Conversations between Paul Ricceur and Gabriel Marcel,"
included in Tragic W i s d o m and Beyond, Evanston, IL:
Northwestern University Press, 1973, trans. Peter McCormick.
____.Gabriel Marcel et Karl Jaspers deux maîtres de L’existentialisme,
Paris: Edition du Temps Présent,1948.
_____."Gabriel Marcel et la phenomenologie," pp. 52-74,
discussion pp. 75-94 in Entretiens autour de Gabriel Marcel :
52
Neuchâtel : à la Baconière, 1976.
G. Marcel and Phenomenology," The Philosophy of Gabriel
Marcel, (The Library of Living Philosophers Vol. XVII), ed. P.
A. Schilpp and L. E. Hahn, LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 1984,
pp. 471-94, Reply by Gabriel Marcel, pp. 495-98.
Schwarz, Balduin V. (ed.) The Human Person and the World of
Values, New York: Fordham University Press, 1960.
Spiegelberg, Herbert. "Gabriel Marcel as a Phenomenologist," pp.
421-44, Vol. 2, The Phenomenological Movement, Historical
Introduction, 2 vols, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1960.
Stern, Karl. "Death within Life," Review of Existential Psychology
and Psychiatry, (Pittsburgh), Vol. 2, No. 2 (1962), pp. 141-44.
Thevenaz, Pierre. "La Philosophie de M. Gabriel Marcel, Une
métaphysique de la présence et la fidelité," Revue
de_Théologie et_de Philosophie, vol. 26, 1938, pp. 235-43.
Thibon, Gustave. "Une Métaphysique de la Communion:
L'
Existentialisme de Gabriel Marcel," Revue de philosophie, 1946,
Paris: Teque, 1947, pp. 144-64.
Troisfontaines, Roger. De l'
existence à l'
etre. La philosophié
de Gabriel Marcel, 2 vols., Louvain, Nauwelaerts, Paris:
Vrin, 1953, 2nd ed. 1968.
____.What is Existentialism?" Thought, Vol. 32, No. 127,
(Winter 1957-58), pp. 516-32.
Tilliette, Xavier. "Gabriel Marcel et l’Autre Royaume" in Jean Wahl et
Gabriel Marcel, Paris: Beauchesne, 1976, pp. 35-56.
____."Gabriel Marcel et le socratisme chrétien," pp. 9-47, in Philosophes
contemporains: Gabriel Marcel, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Karl
Jaspers, Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1962.
Vergote, Antoine. "L"
avenement du Je et l'evenement de verité dans le
temoignage," Temoignage, Paris: Aubier, 1972.
Wahl, Jean. Vers le concret, Paris: Vrin, 1932.
53
addendum: appeared as this work goes to press too late for
consultation but in time for mention in bibliographic references:
GABRIEL MARCEL-GASTON FESSARD CORRESPONDANCE
(1934-1971) présentée et annotée par Henri de Lubac,
Marie Rougier et Michel Sales, introduction par Xavier
Tilliette, Paris: Beauchesne, 1985.
54
55
PART TWO:
DRAMATIC APPROACHES TO CREATIVE FIDELITY
56
Chapter II, The Unfathomable: A Search for Presence
On September 13, 1973, I had the privilege of a two-four conversation
with Gabriel Marcel. Our talk had none of the awkwardness of a first
meeting. Rather, it had been one of my distinct good fortunes as a
philosopher to have first become acquainted with him in Louvain in
1958. Since his four-day visit to Le Moyne College in 1965, I believe it is
not presumptuous to have claimed genuine friendship with this great
philosopher.
In the foreword, I have recounted some of the topics and tone of our
September conversation. Three weeks later, I was back in America and
learned to my sadness that the conversation had been our last. Gabriel
Marcel passed away on October 8, 1973.
Three topics kept appearing and reappearing in that last conversation—
his preoccupation with the presence of loved ones who have gone
beyond death; his concern with the continuing fulfillment of life in the
light of God; and his assurance of a spiritual bond between loved ones
that will not be broken. The topics are so tightly woven to the texture of
human life that they were profoundly moving, even as he spoke. With
his death they took on new meaning. For the three converge in another
theme that was one of Marcel'
s richest sources of philosophic
reflection--that of death and immortality.
In these pages, I would like to present some humble tribute to one who
richly enlarged twentieth-century man's self-understanding and selfappreciation.
The theme I shall consider is that of immortality, from the
perspective of love and interpersonal presence. It is a theme that was
the subject of a continuing existential quest throughout Marcel'
s
lifework. I would hope that the following pages not only illuminate his
past thought, but also reveal the perspective from which his light may
continue to be experienced.
Marcel stated clearly that his concern with death is precisely from
the perspective of one who is concerned for a loved one who has
died.(1) From his point of view, the existential problem of death is the
problem of the conflict between love and death.(2) This unique
perspective on death and immortality, which issues in a
57
phenomenological analysis of survival, is intimately linked with his
conviction that BEING is fundamentally intersubjective.(3)
Thus, following the lead of Marcel's own thought, the precise
question we shall pursue here is that of seeking the nature of the
phenomenon and the conditions that can provide for the continued
Présence of a loved one beyond death. The principal textual sources
we shall draw upon are those published in a book entitled Presence and
Immortality. This book, rich in resources and replete with detailed
critical analyses, was published in English in 1967 by Duquesne
University Press. It includes four works: an essay written in 1937
entitled "My Fundamental Purpose"; entries from Marcel’
s "Metaphysical
Journal for the years 1938-1943"; a 1951 essay entitled "Présence and
Immortality," which, significantly, was originally entitled "The Existential
Premises of Immortality"; and the script of the first act of an unfinished
play, The Unfathomable, written in 1917.
Our procedure will be to first examine the play, as this portrays the
existential situation wherein the death of a beloved person occurs.
Subsequently, we shall trace Marcel'
s critical analysis of the existential
premises of immortality as he articulates these through his philosophic
essays.
For Marcel, it is the art of theater to portray an existential situation.
Thus drama communicates a lived experience and allows us to enter
into its world. In The Unfathomable, we confront a situation that
questions the survival of a loved on. Moreover, the stances of the
different characters invite us to consider critically the alternate opinions
we may have toward someone'
s death.
The central event that gives rise to the drama in the first act of The
Unfathomable is the fact that Maurice Lechevallier has been reported as
missing in action at the end of World War I. The drama portrays the
existential situation wherein the various members of his family react to
the news of Maurice's disappearance. Each construes and interprets
the significance of his fate differently. As the action evolves, it
becomes clear that each ones determination of what Maurice'
s
absence means is to a large extent determined by the attitude that
individual had toward him and the type of relationship they had
shared.
58
Perhaps, as with the two neighbors, Lise Breton and Francine
Vadot, a death may be a subject of curiosity, a topic of gossip. We may
remain insensitive to the fact that this event involves a person whom
others hold as a loved one. Or the stance may be that displayed by
Robert, who proclaims that the facts must be accepted. For him,
Maurice is dead and exists no more. Robert'
s memories fade and
appear to fall short of the reality. He even begins to doubt if he ever
knew his brother at all. Maurice'
s wife, Georgette, fearfully worries
whether she will have him back, or whether she should start a new life
without him. Madame Lechevallier, Maurice'
s mother, really wishes that
he would reappear, for his sake, his wife'
s, and, of course, also her own.
Père Seveilhac insists that Maurice has returned to God and has left his
loved ones for good. They can only pray for him.
The various attitudes conveyed by these characters seem to put in
relief that of Edith, Maurice’s sister-in-law, who accepts that Maurice has
died and mourns him, but enjoys the assurance that he continues to
live, for she experiences the gift of his presence through love, bestowing
refreshment and renewal of life. Three or four of her speeches convey
her sense of experiencing his presence and even intimate the
subjective dispositions requisite for the continued conferral of
intersubjective presence. Her testimony is dramatically poignant.
Edith'
s speeches in her dialogue with Père Seveilhac are
significant for the testimony they present and the description they offer
of the type of experience she witnesses.
Edith (to Père Seveilhac): I can’t say to what extent your
words chill me ....It seams this prayer to which you invite
me exiles me from those for whom it is offered; between
them and us, it puts more than space, it puts God himself.
One can only pray for those who are truly absent, ... but you
can't pretend that death is an absence! There are times
when he is more immediately present to me than he ever
was in life. No longer is there between him and me this
dreadful fear of thinking of one another in a sinful way; no
longer is there the disturbing image of third parties...there are
no longer any third parties. Don'
t give me that harsh look,
Father; I see too clearly that you don't grasp. And yet, you
should remember, you should understand.(4)
59
Edith: ...All that is wrong, all that is outside what I feel and
live.(5)
Edith (in a muffled voice): This feeling of absence that a
dead loved one could not awaken in us. I experience for my
husband with a horrible intensity….He is always at a
distance—and that is not saying enough, for space itself
does not separate those who worship one another. He is
not with me, we are not together; we are...I don'
t know
how to explain to you, ... let us say, like objects placed
near one another, forever outside one another. And yet if
only you knew how passionately I desired that it be
otherwise. (6)
Edith: .. You tell me that nothing outside can respond to my
feeling. I don'
t know what you mean by that. Or rather yes, I
think I know. (With sobs in her throat) Basically,for you,the
dead are no longer there; and your thoughts are in no way
different from those who do not believe. Whatever be the
glorious and unimaginable existence that you ascribe to
them ... for you they are no longer of the living. But for me ...
the truly dead, the only dead are those whom we no longer
love. (7)
Edith: When I think of him in a certain way--with tenderness,
with recollection—there wells up in me something like a
richer, deeper life in which I know he participates.This life is
not I, nor is it he; it is both of us. Shall I admit it to you? I
was hoping a little that you would be able to take part in this
kind of ccnversation without words, the sweetness of
which...(with emotion). Why does it seen to me now that I
am violating a sacred prohibition by telling you that? It is
something about which one must not speak (sternly) with a
stranger. In reality, I have betrayed him.(8)
The lived experience of love and presence, of the assurance of the
survival of a loved one beyond death, an experience that Edith's words
witness and describe, and an experience that can be the reader '
s own, is
the mystery that the philosopher is called upon to analyze and to, clarify.
As Marcel writes in another context: "But the role of the philosopher is to
60
raise to the level of articulated thought what is here only pre-knowledge
and song."(9)
Marcel carries on such critical analysis and reflective clarification
through entries in his "Metaphysical Journal 1938-1943" and in a
phenomenological analysis of survival that animates his essay
"Presence and Immortality."
We can by no means reproduce here the thoroughness of the
detailed analyses and the patient critical probing that Marcel’s thought
brings to bear in questioning the existential premises for the continued
presence of a beloved beyond death. We can, however, trace the main
lines of his thought as he clarifies what he calls the "presential character"
of immortality and uncovers the existential conditions of its possibility.
The major elements Marcel introduces to clarify the presential
character of intersubjective being are: 1) the overcoming of the
categories derived from the model of objects and their relationships, in
order to think of Présence in terms of intersubjective relationships; 2) a
careful investigation of how a subject who is not a physically present
object can nevertheless be actually present, affecting and enriching
the being of a person; and 3) a reflective examination of the significant
difference between possessive desire and the oblative love that animates
hope.
Prior to any understanding of the genuine presential character of
intersubjectivity, it is necessary to overcame the temptation to think of
"presence" in terms of physical objects and those categories proper to
their relationships. Marcel effects this correction of thought by inviting
those who would give such reductionistic interpretations to recognize
the fundamental presupposition implied by their interpretations. The
pretension that being physically near or juxtaposed in space constitutes
"presence" is belied by our own experience as well as by the sense of
Edith'
s remarks. One can be juxtaposed to another in space, be near in
terms of physical proximity, and yet still be alien or distant, far from either
offering or welcoming interpersonal presence. As Edith remarks,
Edith (in a muffled voice): This feeling of absence that a
dead loved one could not awaken in us I experience for my
husband with a horrible intensity.
He is always at a distance--and that is not saying
enough, for space itself does not separate those who
61
worship one another. He is not with me, we are not
together; we are…, I don'
t know how to explain to you,...let
us say, like objects placed near one another, forever
outside one another. And yet if you only knew how
passionately I desired that it be otherwise.(10)
Or as Marcel comments in "Presence and Immortality,"
For instance, we may have the very strong feeling that
someone who is in the room, very close to us, someone
whom we can see and hear and whom we can touch, IS
NEVERTHELESS NOT PRESENT. He is infinitely farther
from us than such a loved one who is thousands of miles
away or who even no longer belongs to our world. What
then is this presence which is here lacking?(11)
Marcel then points out that intersubjective presence, which is of a
completely different order from physical proximity, requires personal
openness, that is, a person's availability to the other'
s appeal or
revelation. In contrast to the distance that estranges the opaque and
self-absorbed individual from his deepest self and frail otters, the open
person, self-possessed and capable of self-giving, is available to be with
and for the other.(12)
In continuing his assertion that physical categories fall short in
any attempt to account for intersubjective presence, Marcel points out
that material communication may take place between two individuals
without the phenomenon of communion that characterizes interpersonal
presence. As he writes in "Presence and Immortality":
It would not be correct to say that we cannot communicate
with this individual who is there very close to us, for he is
neither deaf, nor blind, nor half-witted. Between us a
certain material communication is assured, but only a
material one. It is in every way comparable to the kind
which can be set up between two distinct stations, one
sending and the other receiving. However the essential
thing is lacking. One could say that there is communication
without communion, and for this reason it is unreal
communication.
62
Marcel continues,
The other hears the words that I say; but he does not hear
me and I can be painfully aware that these words, as he
relays them back to me, words which he reflects upon,
become for me unrecognizable.(13)
Thus Marcel observes that it is not material communication that
creates intersubjective presence. Rather it is the openness and the
spiritual exchange of love that create communion. Of an entirely
different order from the transmission of material forms is the co-esse or
the radiant communication of the being of the other person that
constitutes intersubjective communion. In "Presence and Immortality"
he writes,
This experience that I have had a hundred tines is one of
the most mysterious that exists and it appears to me to be
among those to which philosophers have never paid any
attention. One could say that it is, in the best sense,
existential. For it is not so much what the other says, the
content of his words which exercises on me
63
this stimulating action, but it is he himself saying these
words, he himself inasmuch as he sustains his own words
by all that he is.(14)
As Marcel has clarified in other contexts, this communion is a state
of being together in our difference. Such community of being is
constituted as an interpersonal event co-authored by freedoms in the
dialogue of appeal, availability, receptivity, and commitment. Its
enduring quality may be characterized by belonging. Belonging--or the
commitment and creative fidelity of intersubjective being--may be phrased
in affirmations like these: "I am with and for you." "You have at your
disposal all that I am and can be for you." "Your hopes, projects,
fullness of life pertain to me as my own." "I am responsive to your new
questions and new directions of growth; and I will be responsible for
sustaining and supporting them.
Marcel concludes, then, that presence through interpersonal
communion is constituted by the distinctive event "that the other, if I feel
him present, renews me interiorly in some way. This presence is in
such a case revelatory; it makes me more fully myself than I would be
without it."(16) Or as Edith'
s speech expresses it,
When I think of him in a certain way--with tenderness, with
recollection--there wells up in me something like a richer,
deeper life in which I know he participates. This life is not I,
nor is it he; it is both of us. Shall I admit it to you? I was
hoping a little that you would be able to take part in this
kind of conversation without words, the sweetness of
which... (with emotion). Why does it seem to me now that I
am violating a sacred prohibition by telling you that? It is
something about which one must not speak (sternly) with a
stranger. In reality, I have betrayed him.(17)
Thus Marcel has shown. that although physical nearness and
material communication may often be the circumstances in which
presence occurs, they do not account for, nor do they constitute, the
event of interpersonal presence. Moreover, it has become apparent that
presence may occur without these circumstances, for the conditions of
possibility and the distinctive event of interpersonal presence arise from
an entirely different order of being. The requisite conditions for
intersubjective being or events of interpersonal presence are the
64
attitudes that characterize personhood; namely, openness, availability,
and specially that unity and luminescent quality of personhood whereby
one is capable of self-possession and therefore self-giving. Presence is
then constituted by the interaction of people who, in their freedom and grace,
can make that commitment of responsible self-gift to be with and for the other.
And the "substance" of presence reveals itself to be that event or bond of love
whereby the being and life of one and the other are interiorly enriched,
inspired, and supported toward a creative fulfillment that is together hoped
for.
Turning now to the second perspective of questioning, let us consider what can be
the made of presence of the "thou" to "me," especially when that thou is a
beloved beyond death.
Marcel inquires how the other, who is neither a thing nor an objective person, can
nevertheless be present. Or, as he phrases it in "An Essay in Autobiography,"
"Perhaps I can best explain my continual and central metaphysical
preoccupation by saying that my aim was to discover how a subject, in his
actual capacity as subject, is related to a reality which cannot in this context be
regarded as objective, yet which is persistently required and recognized as
real."(18)
The challenge is then to think of the way in which a subject can relate to a reality
that is in no way an object. Since the relationship of communion is conceived
in terms of a bond of spiritual exchange, it is consistent to think of the proper
mode of interpersonal presence in terms of spiritual interaction.
This means that the model of subject object dichotomy, or of a transmission linking
two stations outside each other, should be radically transcended. These models
have a mode of relationship proper to things in a world of objectivity. Love is
the relationship proper to persons in the realm of intersubjectivity. Thus the mode
of conceiving the interpersonal relationship of presence should reflect the way
in which a subject encounters the active influence of another subject who is
with and for him.
Reflecting on the spiritual exchange that characterizes participation in
intersubjective being, Marcel points out that the subject encounters the
spiritual influence of the other by way of interiority or inwardness, as a spiritual
influx or an inward accretion that profoundly affects one's being. Hence the
way toward encountering the presence of the other is through one's own
interiority and depth. The other then becomes present in and through an active
relationship of spiritual influx that enriches and affects one'
s being. Hence the
65
relationship proper to intersubjective being is an encounter of a transcendence
by way of immanence. The subject who possesses or recollects
himself finds that he may participate in or draw upon personalizing
forces that are moreand other than his own alone. The subject who
invokes the presence of the other may find the active influx of a spiritual
influence that bestows benefits that enrich and affect his very being. And
this influx can be recognized as originating in the other as its source.
We find Marcel’
s succinct and positive description of this in "An
Essay in Autobiography."
A presence is a reality; it is a kind of influx; (The word influx,
conveys the kind of interior accretion, of accretion from
within, which comes into being as soon as presence is
effective.) It depends upon us to be permeable to this
influx, but not, to tell the truth, to call it forth. Creative
fidelity consists in maintaining ourselves actively in a
permeable state; and there is a mysterious interchange
between this free act and the gift granted in response to
it.(19)
One might be inclined to identify the structure of presence in
technical terms as the active relationship of encountering an immanent
transcendence. Yet Marcel declines technical terminology, preferring
to articulate the unique phenomenon in the specific language it
presents. I believe this arises from Marcel'
s determination to analyze
and interpret the mystery of presence in a manner faithful to the
evidence given within the experience. I find, moreover, that this
procedure heightens the originality of his interpretation of presence. He
insists on the delicate blending of unity and duality in presence. He
acknowledges its predominant unity as communion yet also
recognizes the intersubjectivity of its coauthoring and being.
He observes that perhaps the idea of relationship with its strong
emphasis on duality is not appropriate to identify presence.(20) He
notes that its unity is stressed and expressed by the statement, "This
life is not I, nor is it he; it is both of us."(21) And, in speaking of creative
fidelity, he points out that the idea of unity of communion in presence is
articulated as "you are with me," which transcends the dualistic and
problematic categories of "before me" or "within me."
66
When I say that a being is granted to me as a presence or
as a being (it comes to the same, for he is not a being for
me unless he is a presence), this means that I am unable
to treat him as if he were merely placed in front of me;
between me and him there arises a relationship which, in a
sense, surpasses my awareness of him; he is not only
before me, he is also within me--or, rather, these
categories are transcended, they no longer have any
meaning. (22)
Even if I cannot see you, if I cannot touch you, I feel that
you are with me; it would be a denial of you not to be
assured of this. With me: note the metaphysical value of this
word, so rarely recognized by philosophers, which
corresponds neither to a relationship of inherence or
immanence nor to a relationship of exteriority. It is of the
essence of genuine co-esse..."(23)
Elsewhere in the same essay he writes:
If presence were merely an idea in us whose characteristic
was that it was nothing more than itself, then the most we
could hope would be to maintain this idea in us or before us,
as one keeps a photograph on a mantelpiece or in a
cupboard. But it is of the nature of presence as presence to
be uncircumscribed; and this takes us beyond the frontier of
the problematical. Presence is mystery in the exact
measure in which it is presence.(24)
Marcel thinks of presence as trans-subjective.(25) Presence is the
sharing, the active participation in the enriched life and being of
intersubjectivity. In this phenomenon the frontier between the I and the
thou is transcended; the essence of presence is the unity of
communion.(26)
Yet presence brings the other to be with one effectively. The
other is really there--in his being, actively constituting the event and
contributing from his uniqueness to the enrichment of the life that
presence provides.
67
Marcel shows that the genuine experience of presence is
characterized by openness and active receptivity, attitudes that both
recognize and highlight the gratuitous and active intervention of the
other that is required to effect the co-constituted event of presence.
In speaking of presence, Marcel maintains the delicate balance
that it depends upon us to be permeable to this influx, but not, to tell the
truth, to call it forth."(27) The one who retains this openness and active
receptivity recognizes that there is a gratuity to the occurrence of that
spiritual influx that constitutes presence. For in the same context Marcel writes of
creative fidelity:
Creative fidelity consists in maintaining ourselves actively in a
permeable state; and (it can be recognized) there is a
mysterious interchange between this free act and the gift granted
in response to it.(28)
And he further points out that a reciprocal fidelity is required for
an active perpetuation of presence, the renewal of its benefits--
of its virtue which consists in a mysterious incitement to
create.(29)
Moreover, he continues,
Thus if creative fidelity is conceivable, it is because fidelity is
ontological in its principle, because it prolongs presence which
itself corresponds to a certain kind of hold which being has upon
us; because it multiplies and deepens the effect of this presence
almost unfathomably in our lives.(30)
And he points out,
This seems to me to have almost inexhaustible
consequences, if only for the relationships between the living
and the dead.(31)
For, as he comments in this essay "On the Ontological Mystery" and in entries
in his "Metaphysical Journal for the years 1938-1943,"
When I say that a being is granted to me as a presence or
as a being (it comes to the same, for he is not a being for me
unless he is a presence)....(32)
68
this involves recognizing that
Revelation is the opposite of inquiry.(33)...and in revealing himself
to me the other somehow draws me to himself; and on condition
that I consent to it, he lifts me out of this world where I tend to be
only a thing among things.(34)
By preserving the delicate balance by thinking of presence predominantly
as a unity of communion, yet also recognizing its duality--as intersubjectivity of
being--through its traits of gratuity and otherness--Marvel metaphysically
situates the subject as one open to an influx of participation in being, as in the
model of artistic creation whereby "the world is present to the artist, to his heart
and to his mind, present to his very being."(35) He thereby transcends the
arbitrary limitations of a metaphysics that considers the subject only as an ego,
closed on itself, or as a cogito hermetically sealed off from other reality,
in which context an immanent experience is interpreted as nothing more than
an isolated nomad's lonely, subjective projections—a poor caricature and
sad travesty of the genuine phenomenon of presence.(36)
In "Presence and Immortality," Marcel introduces the metaphor of
light to further clarify the nature of Presence. He points out that it is only in the
context of a philosophy of light that we can see emerge the deepest
implications of openness for presence and intersubjectivity of being.
He writes,
One could say that intersubjectivity is the fact of being together in
the light. Here as always perhaps, by proceeding negatively
one can approach the positive essence toward which it is
a matter of directing one'
s thought. If, in the presence of
another person I am burdened with mental reservations about him,
or if, which amounts exactly to the same thing, I attribute to
him some ulterior motives concerning me, it is obvious we are
not together in the light. I put myself in the shade. At once, he
ceases to be present to me, and reciprocally, I can no longer be
present to him.(37)
However, he observes in "My Fundamental Purpose,"
69
the world of the other becomes illumined with an increasingly
intense light as the I dispels more of its own darkness and dispels
it more heroically.(38)
He continues,
The more we endeavor to communicate with ourselves--by
that I mean with what in us at first appears as most
recalcitrant to a certain intellectual penetration--the more we
free ourselves from the automatism which is nothing but a
petrifying of our judgment.(39)
So the more closedness is transcended to openness, the more
darkness and estrangement are dispelled to disclose the luminous
quality of ourselves and the luminescent presence of the beloved, until
finally one enjoys a presence that gives rise to an invincible assurance
that is communicated by love. As Marcel writes in conclusion to this
section of the phenomenological analysis of survival in "Presence and
Immortality,"
It expresses itself by some such affirmations as: "I am assured
that you are present to me and this assurance is linked with the
fact that you do not stop helping me, that you help me perhaps
more directly than you could on earth. We are together in the light.
More exactly, in moments when I am detached from myself, when I
cease to eclipse myself, I gain access to a light which is your light.
Surely I do not mean the light of which you are the source, but that
in which you yourself blossom, that which you help to reflect or
radiate upon me."(40)
Thus, intersubjectivity, or being in the presence of one another,
involves an event articulated by freedoms and grace. By presence one's
being and life in its most deeply personal acts is enriched by the active
influx of the other in whose light they are inspired, uplifted, supported,
and sustained. Being together in the light, the other is really and
actively present to me, gracing my being with a light and personalizing
force that I cannot but acknowledge as other and more than my own
alone. For it should indeed be noted that it depends upon me to remain
open and permeable to this gift of presence, but not in fact to call it
forth. As interpersonal presence, its conferral comes as a gratuitous
influx in response to an openness of appeal.(41)
70
The third and final perspective we shall explore for its
significant illumination of the question of presence and immortality
is the difference between desire and hope. Early in "Presence and
Immortality” Marcel states that he finds this difference most
significant if one is to achieve his aspiration to maintaining a living
relationship of active communication with a loved one who has
died. In this section we shall first note the difference between
desire and hope and then explore its significance to the quest to
maintain the presence of a beloved beyond death.
Speaking of the significant difference between desire and hope,
Marcel notes:
This whole investigation could be articulated only by starting
out from what came to me as a discovery--that of the
difference, often ignored even by the most distinguished
persons, between desire and hope.
Desire is by definition egocentric: it tends toward
possession. The other is then considered only in reference
to me, to the enjoyments which he can procure me if I am
full of lust; or he is seen simply in relation to the services
which he will be able to render me. Hope on the other hand
is not egocentric: to hope, I have written in Homo Viator, is
always to hope for us. Let us say that hope is never the
state of wishful thinking which can express itself by an "I
would very much wish that." Hope implies a prophetic
assurance which is really its armor and which prevents the
being from breaking down, internally first of all; but it also
prevents him from giving up, that is to say surrendering or
degrading himself....(42)
He further elaborates the distinction between desire and hope by
pointing out that, on the one hard, desire is structured to that mode of
relationship of "having," which is geared to the possession of a thing,
while hope, on the other hand, is animated by generous love.(43) The
love that animates hope then is not possessive and self-centered, but
rather self-giving and other-directed. Thus he writes, "human love--and
this word is broad enough to be applicable also to friendship, to philia --
implies a reciprocity profound enough to let other-directedness work both
71
ways, to let each become the center for the other. Thus is created a
unity which is no less mysterious than that I spoke of in relation to
incarnation."(44)
Now the attitudes characteristic of "having" must be transcended if
ones quest for active communication with the loved one beyond death
is not to fall short and fail.
Marcel writes:
One can affirm in principle, it seems, that the more the
relationship which has united me to another being has been
strictly possessive, the more his disappearance must come
to be likened to the loss of an object. True, the lost object
can under certain exceptional conditions be found again, but
one cannot attribute to it any presential character.(45)
As one tries to relocate a loved one who has died, there is the
inclination to reach for memories or images recalled from the past. Yet
if this quest yields to the weight of desire, one's search tries to find
something that was lost. One attempts to relocate a person, as an
object, to find him again as he was in the past. Yet this temptation is
frustrating, for the person is no longer there as an object. And the
images or memories one tries to hold and manipulate in this search
become fixed and appear as stale replicas or pale counterfeits of the
sadly desired loved one. As Marcel observes in entries in his
"Metaphysical Journal for the Years 1938-1943," the most this attitude
of desire attains is a reconsideration of images, "like photographs that
one can handle at will; but which images are inert and passive in my
hands."(46) Or, at worst, it may find the object of search as dried
bones or as a notary'
s statistic that inclines one to despair, for these
are but hollow substitutes for the person sought.(47)
Images, memories, replicas of events may serve to give focus to an
inner activity that seeks the actual presence of the beloved. But it is
requisite that the desire for possession be overcome, so that hope
may lead one's aspiration to maintain a living relationship of active
communication with the beloved beyond death. (48)
The attitude of desire toward "having," having the other there as
a subject who .
is an object, having precise services rendered as
demanded in particular circumstances, must be transcended to reach
72
the more genuine attitude of participating in intersubjective being,
admiringly and gratefully being with and for the other and reciprocally
acknowledging that the other remains with and for me.
Let us consider what there is about hope that makes it
indispensable in providing for presence in immortality. Hope is
animated by "oblative" love, a love willing to let go of the other, and
willing to let the other be in a transformed node of life, brings with it an
assurance of a fullness of life for us. In this, hope affects both the
clarification of the conditions of possibility for continued and renewed
presence, and also the tone and focus of one's appeal for that
presence.(49)
First, hope provides assurance of the grounds for a living
relationship of active communication with the actual personal being of
the beloved. For hope carries the assurance that the loved one
continues to live, not merely to exist as sealed off but to be capable of
awareness and capable of responsibility."(50) So while one
acknowledges that the other now lives a transposed mode of life, one
is nonetheless assured that his personal being endures and that the
living reality of intersubjective being will continue to be renewed.
Second, the attitude of hope affects the aim and the tone of one'
s
appeal for presence. For hope, with its "oblative" love and the unity of
reciprocal other-directed human love it provides, is willing to let the other
be in a transposed mode of being, and yet still enjoy the assurance that
the beloved will continue to remain an active center of initiative in coauthoring
the realization of a fullness of life for us.(51) For hope shows
that where there is the reality of an "us," then the fullness of life that the
beloved hopes for essentially involves his continued active
commitment to the realization of that fullness of life with and for me.
Thus the one who hopes counts on the continued complicity of
the beloved's active interventions of creative fidelity to his personal
commitment to bring about the realization of those values that are
essential to a fullness of life for us. In fact, the one who hopes, actively
awaits, and confidently expects that the bestowal of presence--radiating
his light, supporting, sustaining, and uplifting ones personalizing
forces--will be renewed. For the one who hopes enjoys the assurance
that the loved one continues to exist as an actual personhood. As
Marcel phrases it, a "for itself for others".(52)
73
The tracing of a second reflection on Marcel’s theme of Presence
and Immortality enables us to clarify the main lines of this phenomenon
and to identify its essential conditions of possibility.
Negatively, it is neither physical juxtaposition nor material
communication, nor even the relationship of a subject confronting
another person as an object that constitutes presence. Rather
presence occurs through a series of events and relationships that arise
specifically within the order of personal being. Its conditions of
possibility reside in those qualities of personhood that provide requisite
dispositions for the co-authorship of interpersonal events creating the
unity of intersubjective being.
Rather than the subject object dichotomy, the structural model for
thinking of the mode of presence of a loved one from beyond death is
that derived from participation in the mystery of being. Openness
welcomes the increase of personalizing forces that originate from the
other and became resources of one'
s being by way of inward influx.
Hope emerges as primary in grounding and clarifying the
possibility for maintaining the presence of the beloved beyond death.
For hope involves a pre-knowledge as well as a prophetic assurance of
a fullness of life for us. Hope finds in the other person’s being the
assurance of his personal commitment and creative fidelity in enduring
as an active source working in complicity for the realization of a fullness
of life that he wills for us with all his being.
The possibility of establishing and maintaining a living relationship
of active communication with a loved one who has died is rooted in
hope, which, like all interpersonal acts of spiritual exchange, depends
finally on the dialogue of freedom and grace.
One might question the possibilities of ever having a living
relationship with someone three months, three years, or thirty years after
he has died, especially if one has never met or even seen that person
face to face. Yet the key to a response to that question is that whether
we hope or not depends upon us in our freedom.
In the case of Marcel, I believe there are exceptional invitations to
such hope.
74
The style of his philosophy is so strongly personal that he reveals
himself in his concrete approaches, in the articulation of his existential
quest, and by the paths he opens up for personal reflection. Moreover,
his luminescent quality appears, as he phrases it, in that at tines his
words seem to be supported and sustained by all that he is.
Furthermore, his life and work, questioning and reflecting upon the
human condition, respecting its antinomies yet highlighting its noblest
possibilities, is his response to an ontological need for participation in
being, and a clarification of its meaning. This is a communication that is
not exclusively intended as his, but rather fundamentally intended for an
us.
This fundamental purpose, I believe, is the root source of his
protestations against construing or conceiving of anything as his
philosophy. Moreover, this fundamental purpose of communication, I
believe, reveals a deep sense of his preference for neo-Socratic as a
label, if labeling must be done. For the style of his thought is such that it
necessarily respects and awaits the engagement of the other in his or
her own personal philosophizing. For while Marcel portrays concrete
approaches, articulates existential questioning, offers perspectives of
insight, and opens up paths of reflective clarification, still, in order to see the
vision each person must travel the distance on his or her own, making the
experience part of one's personal being, explicating the connection between
steps of reasoning and perspectives of phenomenological analysis, and
deepening a participation in being and clarifying an understanding that
becomes truly one's own.
Thus, to the extent that we aspire to realize fuller and richer forms of
creative fidelity to Marcel'
s inspiration, there indeed appear to be strong grounds
on his part assuring that the light of his presence will be there.
75
Notes to Chapter II. The Unfathomable: A Search for Presence
1. "Presence and Immortality," in Presence and Immortality,
Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press, 1967, p. 230-31; "An
Essay in Autobiography," in The Philosophy of Existentialism,
New York: Citadel, Philosophical Library, 1961, p. 112-13.
2. "Presence and Immortality," p. 231.
3. "Presence and Immortality," p. 239; "My Fundamental
Purpose," in Presence and Immortality, pp. 24 and 26.
4. "The Unfathomable," in Presence and Immortality, p. 274.
5. Ibid., p. 275.
6. Ibid., pp. 275-76.
7. Ibid., p. 277.
8. Ibid., p. 280.
9. "Presence and Immortality," p. 232.
10. "The Unfathomable," pp. 275-76.
11. "Presence and Immortality," p. 237.
12. "On the Ontological Mystery," in The Philosophy of
Existentialism, New York: Citadel, Philosophical Library, 1961,
pp. 39-40; "My Fundamental Purpose," pp. 27-29.
13. "Presence and Immortality," p. 237.
14. Ibid., p. 238.
15. Creative Fidelity, New York: Noonday Press, Farrar, Straus
and Co., 1964, p. 40-42.
16. "Presence and Immortality," p. 38, citing Mystery of Being,
Volume I, Chicago, Regnery, Gateway Edition, 1960, pp. 220-
21.
76
17. "The Unfathomable," p. 280.
18. "An Essay in Autobiography," p. 127.
19. "On the Ontological Mystery," p. 38.
20. "Presence and Immortality," p. 238.
77
21. "The Unfathomable," p. 280.
22. "On the Ontological Mystery," p. 38.
23. Ibid., p. 39.
24. Ibid., p. 36.
25. "Presence and Immortality," p. 238.
26. "Metaphysical Journal for the Years 1938-1943," in Presence
and Immortality, p. 176.
27. "On the Ontological Mystery," p. 38.
28. Ibid.
29. Ibid., p. 36.
30. Ibid.
31. Ibid.
32. Ibid., p. 38
33. "Metaphysical Journal for the Years 1938-1943," May 14,
1943, p. 173.
34. Ibid., May 17, 1943, p. 177.
35. "On the Ontological Mystery," p. 36.
36. "Presence and Immortality," pp. 230, 240-44.
37. Ibid., p. 239.
38. "My Fundamental Purpose," p. 27.
39. Ibid., p. 28.
40. "Presence and Immortality," p. 242.
78
41. "Metaphysical Journal for the Years 1938-1943," May 3, 1943, p.
153.
42. "Presence and Immortality," pp. 231-32.
43. Ibid., p. 235.
44. Ibid.
45. Ibid.
45. "Metaphysical Journal for the Years 1938-1943," May 31,
1942, p. 79.
46. "Presence and Immortality," pp. 230, 243; "Metaphysical
Journal for the Years 1938-1943," p. 209.
47. "Metaphysical Journal for the Years 1938-1943," May 31,
1942, p. 88.
48. Ibid., p. 89-90.
49. Ibid., April 26, 1943, p. 142; May 17, 1943, p. 177; August 7,
1943, p. 207-8.
50. Ibid., August 15, 1943, p. 217.
51. Ibid., August 19, 1943, p. 217.
79
Chapter III. The Lantern : and The Light of Truth
In the William James lectures he delivered at Harvard University
Gabriel Marcel voiced his hope that American audiences might soon
know concretely how, in the case of his work, the theater is a privileged
way of access to the philosophic reflections. For theater played a
privileged role in the development of Gabriel Marcel’s thought.(1)
In this chapter I would like to look with you at The Lantern, a oneact
play by Gabriel Marcel that stands in the permanent repertory of the
National Theater of France, La Comédie Française.(2) I hope that our
analysis of The Lantern will reveal something of the nature of Marcel's
drama and also the peculiar role that theater played in the development
of his thought. Through this consideration of The Lantern we also intend
to examine a central question raised by the play, namely, "What might it
mean to see or to live in the light of Truth?"
Our procedure will be as follows. We will first give a brief synopsis
of the play and identify the questions it gives rise to. Then in a second
moment of Gaareflection we shall clarify these issues, reconstructing
the action of the play to bring to light perspectives of insight on them.
And from time to time we shall amplify interpretations by drawing on
statements that Marcel articulated years later on the explicitly
philosophic level of rational analysis. A third moment will propose some
summary conclusions to this study.
The Lantern, written December 26-28, 1935, has as its setting a
Paris apartment, the home of Raymond Chavière. The play explores
Raymond’s situation after the death of his mother, Elizabeth
Parmentier, and focuses on the question of where and how Raymond
will live now that his mother has died. The drama portrays the various
options proposed to Raymond, and a surprise ending to the play shows
how Raymond makes his own choice. True to the hallmark of Marcel'
s
theatrical style, the drama presents the heightening of Raymond'
s
consciousness, communicating it as it were from within, so that
audiences too can participate in the mysterious experience that
Raymond lived.(3)
The play begins with Madame Andrezy, the housekeeper, showing
in Mr. Anton Chavière. She fails to recognize him as Raymond'
s father,
for he has not come to the house since his divorce from Madame
80
Parmentier. When Raymond enters, father and son greet coldly. Mr.
Chavière, who could not get there for the funeral, tells Raymond that he
has come now to see if by chance before going she had not left some
sort of message for him, and also to ask Raymond if now that his mother
has passed on he would not like to come and live with Chavière and
Isabelle at their house on Marignan Avenue. Raymond parries this
query with the curt statement that this would be awkward now, as he is
engaged to be married to Sabine Verdun. There follows a heated
exchange between father and son about the mothers approval of this
proposed marriage and also about the church'
s teaching on matrimony.
As Chavière prepares to leave, Sabine Verdun, Raymond'
s
fiancée, arrives. She, for her part, encourages Raymond to go away
with her for a holiday of rest and recreation. Raymond becomes
angered by Sabine's saying that this is what his mother would have
wanted, for certainly such was not the case.
As Sabine Verdun is leaving, Chavière's second wife, Isabelle,
who is ravishing, arrives. She asks Raymond to come and live with his
father and her, to add a little interest to their lives. And certainly if he
came to live with than, she would not hesitate to add some tenderness
to his life. Otherwise she is on the verge of leaving with Olivier Guerin,
Sabine'
s former husband, for the Orient. Raymond points out to
Isabelle their weakness and the flaw and ambiguity in her proposal.
Anton Chavière returns to see if Raymond has made up his mind
about Anton'
s invitation to come and live with them in the house on
Marignan Avenue. Father and son chat, apparent small talk about the
apartment, a book by Blondel, the Van der Weyden exhibit this season.
Isabelle, feeling herself superfluous, leaves. Then Raymond gently tells
his father that Isabelle will be away for a while--perhaps she didn'
t dare
mention it to you, but she had wanted to spend a fortnight with a friend
in the country before that friend left on a trip to Japan or India or
someplace like that. Anton interjects, "She didn'
t say a word to me."
Raymond continues, "So then I thought… perhaps it will seem strange
to you …" Anton: "What is it, my son?" Raymond:"That while Isabelle
will be with her friend, you'
d come and live here." Anton (with emotion):
"It would be just the two of us." Raymond (gravely): "
No, father--the
three of us, as before . . . as never before."(4)
The play ends on that surprising note. It leaves us unsettled and
bemused. Marcel plays often have surprise endings. He noted that the
81
end of a play is most important not only for the unity it brings to the
whole play but also for the questions it raises.
The end of The Lantern leaves us wondering. What does that
ending mean? More precisely, we wonder where that decision came
from. Is it an act of compliance or rebellion in reaction to other"
expectations, or is it a genuinely personal choice, one that can be called
an act of creative fidelity? We also wonder how Raymond came to that
decision. How did he evolve the idea of inviting his father to come home
with him? This decision goes against the flow that the proposals and
actions of others were suggesting. Where did Raymond'
s idea come
from? How did it emerge in his consciousness? Or, in other words, how
did Raymond come to see in the light of truth?
The end of a Marcel play not only poses questions, it also opens
up perspectives of light. Thus the ending of The Lantern stimulates
audiences to reflect on the questions raised, not only as these issues
influence the lives of characters in the play but also as these mysteries
are part of the lives of spectators as well. Thus audiences are invited,
by the startling effect of the ending of The Lantern, to reconstruct the play
in reverse, in the light of the questions raised, in order to see how
Raymond came to the decision he did. This is exactly what we shall do
in the second part of this chapter. We shall reconstruct the action of the
play to help us clarify, by reflection on the drama, what it might mean to
see and live in the light of truth.
The very title of the play, as well as its last lines, suggest that the
light of truth refers to Madames Parmentier's Présence after her
death. There is not only the title, The Lantern, and the last lines, "It
would be just the two of us?" "No, father - the three of us, as before..
.as never before ...” There is also Raymond'
s speech wherein he refers
to his mother as being for them like a lantern.(5) Raymond's dawning
consciousness in this soliloquy is the crucial moment in his change of
attitude. It also marks the transition from his perceiving his mother as a
sometimes oppressive third person between them (Raymond and
Sabine, and Raymond and Chavière) to his perceiving her as an
intimate light or a presence known by way of interiority and depth.(6)
Let us begin to reconstruct the action of the play. Madame
Parmentier is very much present in the action of the first few scenes.
In fact, it seems as if Madame Parmentier is a major figure in the play,
82
although she never appears on stage except in terms of the aura of light
she seems to radiate into people'
s lives.
There is a coolness and a strained sense of distance
characterizing Raymond's meeting with his father after his mother's
death. Raymond has developed a sense of estrangement if not of
resentment in relation to his parents' divorce. In the early conversation
with his father, Raymond is defensive of his mother's good name, very
protective of his memory of her. The father comes hesitantly and
confusedly seeking some closeness, some form of reconciliation. He
asks if Raymond's mother might have left some sort of message for
him before going. He also asks Raymond to come and live with them,
now that his mother is dead. Raymond refuses this invitation rather
abruptly, announcing that he is engaged and soon to be married to
Sabine Verdun. When Anton asks if Raymond'
s mother approved of
her son'
s betrothal to a divorced woman, father and son quarrel.
Raymond had not told his mother of his plans. Anton and
Raymond argue about readiness for marriage and the wisdom of the
church's discipline and teaching about the holiness of matrimony.
There is a tragic irony about the argument, because basically the ideas
the father proposes in advising his son are the very ones the parents'
divorce seems to belie. (7)
When Sabine Verdun arrives, Raymond remains upset, deeply
troubled by the argument and his father'
s visit. Sabine'
s advice to
Raymond is that he and she should go away for a holiday together.
The rest would do him good, and that is what his mother would have
wanted. Raymond reacts. Taken together, his fathers question of
whether his mother knew and approved of his project to marry a
divorced woman, and now Sabine'
s subtle but incisive observations
and even her insistence that Raymond'
s mother would have wanted
them together to enjoy themselves on a holiday, these events get to
Raymond. He is angered and then thrown back on his own resources.
In reaction to these upsetting references to his mother, Raymond gets
in touch with what he really knew her to be. He recalls their relation,
the closeness they shared. He begins to remember her as she really
was. (8) And in that moment he becomes aware of the deception and
rebellion that had come to characterize his life in relationship to Sabine
Verdun.
83
In the famous soliloquy, wherein Raymond refers to his mother'
s
Présence as the beam of a lantern, he acknowledges that he and
Sabine were deceiving themselves as well as his mother. They were
taking advantage of the terrible weakness that death brings. Raymond
admits that he was living a rebellion, like a slave taking revenge that he
didn'
t even enjoy. Further, he even recognizes that he, who never lied,
had lied to his mother about his relationship with Sabine. He had said,
when the mother asked about her, "Oh, Sabine Verdun? A friend, very
intelligent, perhaps a little heartless." He had said that to reassure her.
"To say, 'perhaps a little heartless,'
about a woman, that was clear
proof that one had no intention ..."(9) He finds that they acted
despicably, especially himself, taking advantage of his mother'
s
weakness, waiting for her to die so that they, Sabine and he, could be
free for the good life to begin. Recalling his true relationship with his
mother, Raymond recognizes his deception of her and of himself, and
he sees his resentful rebellion for the foolish act that it was. Raymond
now realizes that he will probably not marry Sabine Verdun. Their
relation was just a fantasized escape from the demands of an
extraordinary woman and the resentful revenge of one who suffered from
his parents'
divorce.
As Raymond remembers his mother, he begins to perceive his life
situation more clearly, and he seems better able to evaluate the different
options proposed to him as temporary living arrangements after his
mother’s death.
We have just seen what is a significant step in ones opening to see
in the light of truth. Namely, the first moment of coming to see in the light
of truth is a moment of recognition that one has previously been living in
untruth; that is, one has been deceiving oneself and others.
Acknowledgement that one has been living a life of deception, selfdeception
as well as deception of others, usually occurs as it happened
for Raymond. It is in the light of another persons Présence that the light
dawns. One perceives the self-deception and can begin to be freed
from it.
In a philosophical essay written several years after The Lantern,
Marcel developed this idea on a philosophical level.(10) A corollary of
what he wrote is that the more I am open to the light of the Présence of
another person, the more I can see and communicate in a light of truth.
In proportion as I cease to eclipse myself from their light, I can
increasingly live and see in the light of my own truth. (11) It was first
84
through theater and his dramatist'
s sensitivity to the currents of
interaction between various people that Marcel perceived this reality.
It was only later, in subsequent reflection, that the idea became clear
for Marcel on a philosophic level of analysis.(12)
In the play The Lantern, the concrete portrayal of Raymond'
s
coming to a decision reveals the way one can come to see in a light of
truth. Once Raymond, in the light of his mother'
s Présence, recognizes
his own self-deception in his attempt with Sabine to deceive his
mother, he begins to see clearly into not only that maneuver but also
into the other options coming into his field of choice and, perhaps most
important, into the true desires of his own heart. We shall see how this
develops through the remainder of the play.
In scene five, Sabine leaves. There is an air of finality about her
departure. After Sabine has left, Isabelle confides in Raymond and
exposes the particular idea of how it could be helpful to Anton
Chavière if Raymond would come and live with them. Raymond listens
and then clarifies by a question what was confused in her proposal.
Was it for his father or for her that Isabelle had asked Raymond to
come and live with them? Raymond also brings to light what was
dangerous in her proposal, the inevitability that if Isabelle and
Raymond lived under the same roof, in two months they would become
lovers, a disgraceful situation that would not be any real help to any of
the three of them.
Raymond sees the accuracy of Sabine's cruel prediction that Anton
and Isabelle’s household will not survive the death of Raymond's
mother. Raymond sympathizes with Isabelle"
s weakness but also sees
through the unconscious treachery of her confusion. Yet while
Raymond sees clearly, he does not judge harshly or condemn. At this
moment, with great balance, Raymond invokes the memory of his
relationship with his mother, a relationship of great intimacy with
moments of happiness and also of some suffering, a relationship
suffused with admiration yet difficult for fear of the disappointment some
show of weakness might cause. So excellent a creature as she is bound
to create a great deal of suffering about her.(13) So while Raymond
sees where the plans lead and refuses to go along with them, he does
not judge the people. He understands why and how the people involved
think and feel the way they do. He also sees how the differences
among them have contributed to the tragic situation in which they
85
unhappily find themselves. Raymond seems not to judge but rather to
understand with a blend of lucidity and compassion.
Raymond seems, in this respect, to incarnate the kind of
sympathetic understanding that drama can develop in an audience, a
clear-sighted compassion that leads people to see a tragic situation as
it were from an overarching perspective, not condemning or judging but
rather saying with genuine compassion, "You are understood."(19) And
Raymond recognizes that he too is in need of this compassionate
understanding as well as being called upon to give it.(15)
As the play moves toward its denouement we can see how
Raymond formed his decision. Raymond perceives the options
proposed to him as the "apparent goods" that they are. He refuses to
follow the direction of others that leads to splitting off from family ties. Not
only does he foresee the unhappy consequences prepared by such
fragmentation of family, a brokenness of heart and relationships such
as he has already experienced through his parents' divorce, but also,
and perhaps more important for the sake of good decision-making, he
comes very much in touch with the values he wants to love and live by
and make his own. In saying no to options proposed by others,
Raymond gets more deeply in touch with himself and becomes
aware of his own deepest longing for family unity and interpersonal
relations that last.
Raymond'
s initiative in inviting his father home, to come and
live together again, is the result of Raymond'
s progressive
clarification of his perspective on the situation. Thanks to his
willingness to heed a perspective of light that his mother'
s presence
radiates, Raymond has moved from rebellious self-deception and
deception of others to compassionate understanding of a tragic
situation that involves oneself and others. He has come to
recognize the options of alternate life-styles for what they are and,
by way of contrast, to recognize the desires of his own heart for a
deep and lasting relationship of love and interpersonal family
relations that abide.
Raymond'
s decision is no act of conformity or rebellion, merely
reacting for or against the expectations of others. Raymond'
s choice
is a genuine act of creative fidelity. There is something spontaneous
and original about his offer. Moreover, it springs from his own deep
vital center and expresses his personal choice of how he wants to
86
live. Confirmation of these as essential characteristics of genuine acts
of creative fidelity is articulated years later on a philosophic level in
the book entitled Creative Fidelity. (16)
Raymond, in moving beyond the apparent confines of a tragic
situation, has fallen back on his own deepest resources and in
drawing upon these has created a new form of fidelity to those
persons and values that he wants to restore and preserve in his life.
Thus Raymond'
s personal decision and creative initiative are
resourced in his genuine fidelity--his faithfulness in affection and
responsibility toward his father, his faithfulness to his own hope for
family unity and interpersonal relations that abide, and faithfulness to
what his mother longed and lived for, although she did not see it
realized during her earthly existence.
In the play The Lantern, the light of truth that illumines
Raymond'
s understanding of his situation and his act of creative
fidelity in response to that situation is not just some theoretic
knowledge or dialectic argumentation; rather it is the light of a personal
presence, the presence of his mother from beyond death.
In Raymond'
s soliloquies wherein he evokes his mother, he
alludes to two different modes of presence, one during earthly life when
her presence was like that of a third person who was almost
overwhelming, and the other a presence through real intimacy as when
we encounter another'
s presence by way of inwardness and depth.
Marcel observed in a private conversation shortly before his own
death that he preferred to speak of presence from beyond death
as "living in the light of”.(17) After death one can sense in a more
intense and purified way who the beloved really was and what it was
that he or she really loved and lived for. It is in this manner of
openness to his mother'
s presence, who she was and what she
loved, that Raymond came to live in the light of truth and to pose
his choice of how he would live his life after her death. His choice
was consciously and freely his own, yet its inspiration was in a
shared light, a light that was other and more than his alone. As
Marcel wrote in reflections on presence from beyond death, after
death the loved one can continue to be present although in a
transformed way.(18) Privileged moments of renewal of the loved
one'
s presence, which it depends upon us to be open to but not in
fact to summon forth, occur by way of inwardness and depth and
87
they bring an uplifting of our being and an incitement to create.
(19)
It is in this manner that we can understand that light of truth in
which Raymond came to make his startling decision at the end of
The Lantern. It is likewise in this context that we can begin to
fathom the meaning of Raymond'
s final remark.No father--the three
of us, as before. . . as never before."(20)
An Endnote
It is possible, upon reflection, for someone to see the way
Raymond lived in the light of truth as representative of the way one
can live life in the light of faith. There are subtle and discrete
intimations of this in the play. There is first the fact that while all
the other characters situate themselves explicitly in relationship to
faith, Raymond simply lives the witness of his. There is also a
stage direction indicating a Van der Weyden print as part of the set.
This artist was noted for vivid colors, for drawing subjects in three
dimensions, and for portraying the religious in everyday
settings.(21)
Marcel cautions that he finds it inappropriate for theater in our
times to try and show God directly, but he observes that theater
can show the working of grace as it operates in peoples'
lives.(22)
Such witness, he offers, could be an appropriate presentation of
religion in theater, but it would be successful only to the extent that
this effect was not calculated or intentional.
It is perhaps, as Marcel wrote à propos of his philosophy, as if
our reflections are drawn toward a light of a higher order that
philosophy perceives from afar and of which it suffers the secret
attraction.(23) Marcel’s philosophic reflections do invite another level of
personal reflection on the part of those who wish to consider these
issues and insights explicitly in the light of religious faith. In the context of
Christian faith, the light of Truth is assuredly a personal Présence from
beyond death. One has only to recall the sacred scriptures celebrated
between the feast of Easter and Pentecost.(24)
88
Notes to Chapter III. The Lantern: and The Light of Truth
1. The Existential Background of Hunan Dignity, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1963.
2. Le Fanal, December 26-28, 1935, was commissioned for the
1937-38 season of the Comédie Française by its director Edourd
Bourdet. The script was published in Paris, ed. Stock, 1938. Le
Fanal was published in English translation by Elizabeth Stambler
and Joseph Cunneen in Cross Currents Vol. VII, No. 2., Spring
1958, pp. 129-43.
3. "The Drama of the Soul in Exile" introduction to Three Plays by
Gabriel Marcel: A Man of God, Ariadne, The Votive Candle, New
York, Hill and Wang, Mermaid Drama book, 1965, p. 22.
4. The Lantern, Scene VII, p. 143.
5. Ibid., Scene IV, p. 137.
6. Ibid., Scene IV, p. 137, Scene VI, p. 142.
7. Ibid., Scene II, p. 133.
8. Ibid., Scene IV, p. 137, cf. also Scene VI, p. 142.
9. Ibid., Scene IV, pp. 136-37.
10. "My Fundamental Purpose" (1937) in Presence and Immortality,
Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press, 1967, pp. 13-30.
11. Ibid., pp. 26-27. "I shall note in passing that no philosophical text
has impressed me more strongly than the one in which the American
philosopher, W. E. Hocking, in his book The Meaning of God in
Human Experience, has established that we cannot really conceive
an apprehending of the other which is not truly an apprehending of
ourselves and which confers on our experience its human weight....
the world of the others becomes illumined with an increasingly
intense light as the I dispels more of its own darkness and dispels it
more heroically." Cf. pp. 24, 20, 18, 16.
12. Ibid., pp. 13-15.
89
13. The Lantern, Scene VI, pp. 141-42.
14. "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," p. 21, "My Dramatic Works as
Viewed by the Philosopher" (1959) in Searchings, New York:
Newman Press, 1967, pp. 111, 117.
90
15. The Lantern, Scene VI, pp. 141-42, cf."The Drama of the Soul in
Exile," p. 32.
16. Creative Fidelity, New York: Farrar, Straus & Co., 1964, pp. 107,
109; cf. also Home Viator, New York: Harper & Bros., 1962, pp.
129-34.
17. The Heights, Le Moyne College, December 1973, pp.17-18
18. Presence and Immortality, "Presence and Immortality," pp.
235-39.
19. The Philosophy of Existentialism, New York: Citadel Press, 1956, On
the Ontological Mystery, pp. 38, 36, cf. The Lantern, SceneVI, p.
141.
20. The Lantern, Scene VII, p. 143.
21. The Lantern, Scene VII, p. 142.
22. Théâtre et Religion, Lyon, Vitte, 1958, "L'
idée du drame
chrétien dans son rapport au Théâtre actuel" (1957), pp. 76-
86, cf. also The Philosophy of Existentialism, "Testimony
and Existentialism", p. 98, "…. testimony is based on fidelity to
a light, or to use another language, to a grace received."
23. The Philosophy of Existentialism, "On the Ontological
Mystery," p. 46.
24. Philosophic reflection and inquiry are drawn toward the fuller light
of faith. Scriptures relating presence beyond death of Jesus Christ from the
Resurrection to Pentecost: Matthew 28:1-10, 16-20; John 20:1-18; Luke
24:13-35; John 20:19-23; John 16:7; 14:14-21; 14:16, 17, 26; 14:23-
29.
91
Chapter IV. Dot The I: An Existential Witness of the Light of Truth
During his lifetime Gabriel Marcel (1889-1973) often expressed
the hope that his theater and philosophy would be recognized as
essentially complementary, that his dramatic and philosophic works
would be studied together, heard in concert. Introducing his 1961-1962
William James Lectures at Harvard University, Marcel expressed his
regret that reader awareness of the substantial connections linking his
theater and philosophy was unfortunately all too abstract. Throughout
the course of these lectures, later published under the title The
Existential Background of Human Dignityy, he stressed the importance
of studying his dramatic and philosophic works as complementary
modes of inquiry and clarification.(l)
The theme of this chapter, "Existential Witness of the Light of
Truth," is especially well suited for this integral approach. The theme, of
itself, seems to invite dramatic representation. Existential witness refers
to the fact that a certain quality of truth is communicated not merely by
the words one says, but rather by the fact that these words are
supported by the very life and being of the one who speaks them.
Communication in the light of truth refers to the fact that one
person can lovingly share a communication of what he or she lives by in
such a way that another person begins to see in a light of truth what he
or she lives by, or, perhaps even more important, can hope to live by.
Drama can depict existential witness and communication in the
light of truth. Drama can enable audiences to be touched by existential
witness. Drama also lets spectators enter into a dialogic communication
in the light of truth, one that brings into question not only the lives of the
characters in the play but the lives of individual spectators as well.
Dot the I, Les points sur les i, written November 6-9, 1936, raises
questions about the light of truth.(2) The action of the play shows that
existential witness is key in the communication of a light of truth.
Dot the I portrays the situation of three liberal-minded adults who
attempt to live a three-way marriage. The Girondin household includes
Anatole, the playwright and husband; Irma, his mistress and muse; and
Felicia, his housekeeper and wife. Also living with them is Amy, (whose
name in French: “Aimée”, means “the loved one”). She is the twelve-
92
year-old daughter of Irma. Amy is only there temporarily, having
accompanied her mother. There was no place for Amy at her fathers
home in the south after his new wife, the mother of Amy's baby brother,
moved in. There's talk of finding Amy an "au pair" situation where she
can live and work with a family.
As the play begins it is difficult to figure out who's who, how the
characters relate to one another, and where they fit into the household
arrangement. It is evident that there is irritating friction between the two
women, Felicia, the wife, and Irma, the live-in mistress.
Each person has a different interpretation of the situation. Anatole
reminds Felicia that when she generously agreed to this arrangement
she became obliged to a civility and considerateness that is necessary
if they are to succeed at living this human experiment, feasible only for
those noble spirits who are beyond the prejudices and small minded
constraints of middle-class morality. Felicia reminds Anatole that she
likes to keep it perfectly clear what the situation is. Irma is there only by
Felicias leave. Felicia can end the experiment just by saying so, any
time she wants. What’s more, the child will not stay long. They find a
place for her "au pair." Irma reminds Felicia that they are all better off
now than they were before Irma came to live with them. The situation
then was that Anatole was gone all night, or coming home at all hours
and with "ladies of the night," or taking off for trips to Belgium. Now at
least he's home, steady and working. That's better for all of them. Amy
is not complicated and does not bother her head trying to sort out or
explain that level of situations. She tries to fit in, be helpful, and not
bother others, who she knows really don't want her around.
The fragile fiction that the adults have fabricated is threatened
when Felicia hears that Irma and Anatole plan to spend the weekend in
the country passing as Mr. and Mrs. Girondin and staying at the estate
of a socially prominent couple, Lucien and Blanche Foucard. This they
propose on the pretense of wanting to gain political influence to
promote the production of Anatole's play “Robespierre” so that it will
premiere at the National Theater. Felicia is furious that things have
gone too far. She senses that she is powerless now that events are
beyond her control. She has been ignored and excluded. Moreover,
she is humiliated to the breaking point when, in her own home, she is
not introduced or presented as the person she really is. Irma introduced
her to the Foucards as Mrs. Rosary, a relative who is unfortunately
suffering from painful facial neuralgia.
93
After the two couples have gone out, Felicia sends Amy to run
and tell her mother that Felicia says she is going to tell Amy the whole
truth, everything. She says she is going to dot the i's... that is to give a
full and complete explanation.
While Amy runs to catch up to her mother and give her the
message, Felicia goes to the window, looks out and then abruptly
closes the shutters and the drapes and turns on the electric lamps,
even though it is broad daylight outside. Felicia sits in this semi
obscured, artificially illuminated room. When Amy reenters the living
room, the stage is set for the final confrontation.
We are prepared to hear Felicia tell Amy the harsh facts of life,
projecting her own perceptions and sense of rejection onto the child,
informing her that she is unwanted and unloved. But we find that the
conversation takes a surprise turn and moves in unexpected directions.
With dramatic irony the child becomes mother to the woman, and the
light of truth appears to be not the dreadful harsh light of resentment,
recrimination, and rejection, but rather a childlike light of faith
communicating a remarkably mature experience of forgiveness and
love.
The conversation starts out very tentatively, then moves to kindly,
friendlier sharings, and finally yields some startling exchanges of
confidence and understanding love.
At first the exchanges are touchy if not hostile. Amy inquires
about Felicia’s health and apologetically assures her that she doesn't
mean to bother her. Amy asks Felicia not to speak harshly, for Felicia
has nothing for which to reproach Amy. Amy has done nothing to hurt
Felicia, at least not deliberately.
When Felicia asks whether Amy didn't really want to get to Paris,
Aired reveals the truth that she would have liked to have stayed at her
father's house with her baby brother, but that there was no room for her
after her father remarried. When Amy shows pictures of her baby
brother and dissolves in tears, telling of her fear that he'll forget her if
she is never able to go and see him, Felicia shows kindness and pity
and assures the girl that they’ll arrange some way for her to go and visit.
The conversation continues in a friendlier vein. Amy asks what
94
does “dot the I’s" means, and Felicia responds that it is only a cliché
that does not really mean much. Amy asks what kind of work she might
do "au pair," to which Felicia replies in a motherly tone that maybe she’d
take care of little children. She'd love that, Amy exclaims. She adds that
when she’s married she's going to have twins right away, a boy and a
girl. It seems that one can choose. Father Simone’s friends talk that
way, and they seem to decide and choose. Felicia states that it's not
always a question of choice; she then blurts out that she'd lost twins
and was told by the doctors that if she tried to bear children again she'd
die in childbirth.
Amy commiserates with Felicia and then, trying to console her,
affirms that Felicia's twins are angels in heaven. This draws a joking
and mocking reaction from Felicia. Amy asks Felicia if she doesn't ever
repent and confess. Felicia's reply is that she has no need to, that she
has nothing for which to reproach herself. Amy declares her need. She
says that if she didn't confess she'd die. It would be as if she couldn't
breathe, as if her soul would suffocate and die. But, she adds, the soul
doesn't die because the soul is immortal. Entangled in language, Amy
leaves off theological discussion to share a confidence.
Amy admits that when she heard that she'd have to leave her
father's house and not see her brother for a long time she felt shocked
and hurt. She even wished that her stepmother would die so that Amy
could stay with her father and be a little mother to her baby brother. But
then she was ashamed, for some feel that a thought is something real,
like a weapon that can hurt people. Amy felt guilty and ashamed, and
didn't dare to look at her stepmother or to go to confession. But the
priest who'd helped her prepare for confirmation saw something in her
eyes and was kind to her. That helped her find courage to go to
confession. Then she affirms, "Those thoughts left me, I felt light and
happy."
Felicia protests but breaks down, letting tears flow and a new light
of truth be born into her life. She protests that she s beyond reproach.
She did what was best. Few would have had that courage. It’s the
others who are wrong. Amy interjects, "Those others who hurt you."
Felicia continues, "If I'd only had a child like you. The little bit I had, I
wanted to keep." Amy asks, "Those others who have hurt you, cousin,
are they....?" Felicia shakes her head as if to convey that she cannot
answer. Amy continues and gets tearful nods from Felicia. "That is none
of my business? I shall never know? I have perhaps guessed, you
95
know."
The dialogue continues:
Felicia: No.
Amy: You don't want me to guess?
Felicia: I don't want it, I don’t want it anymore.
Amy: You’re crying now like a child…like a little child, my cousin.
(She drops to her knees; she puts her arms around Felicia’s neck.)
Marcel's plays usually have a surprise ending. The final scene is
most important, both for dramatic unity it provides to the play and for the
questions it raises for the audience. At the end of this play we find many
questions are raised. What does it mean to "dot the i's"? Can one give
the full and complete explanation of a human situation especially as it
involves freedoms in interpersonal relationships? What is it to see and
judge in the light of truth? Is it to see with childlike simplicity or with adult
sophistication? Is it to judge blame, fault, and incrimination, or is it to
come to a compassionate understanding through forgiving love?
The one question the limits of this chapter allows us to focus on,
and that only with a cursory view of its highlights, is: What is the nature
of the existential witness and the communication in the light of truth that
we see happening in the lives of Amy and Felicia in the last scene of
Dot the I ?(4) In the final scene Amy shares an existential witness that
enables Felicia to begin to see her life and revise its meaning in a new
light of truth.
In a loving and confiding manner Amy tells Felicia her secret.
Amy, like Felicia, knew rejection and felt the pain of love’s loss. She
was so terribly hurt that she bitterly resented the one who replaced her,
hated her and almost wished that she'd die. Yet Amy adds that these
thoughts of hatred and resentment and the feelings of shame and guilt
that accompanied than almost suffocated her. Then someone was
compassionate toward her, and that helped her find the courage to
confess. When she confessed and renounced those feelings, the
thoughts that had hurt her left and she felt light and happy.
Amy's witness includes the story she tells, but it also conveys the
reality and light of truth she lives by. Amy shares this communication in
a genuinely loving way. She feels compassion for Felicia and hopes
that Felicia too can be set free. It is in this spirit that Amy shares her
message that to let go of hatred and judgments of condemnation lets
96
one be free to live and feel love. Amy shares with Felicia the very reality
she lives, namely that forgiveness opens the way for love and hope to
reenter one's soul.
The communication of a light of truth touching both their lives was
enabled by a genuine spirit of love and trust. Felicia's opening to the
light of truth Amy communicates also entails Felicia 's opening by way
of inwardness and depth to her own light of truth.(5) Though at first she
protested, Felicia is able gradually to let go of judgments of resentment
and condemnation. With Amy's compassion, Felicia is able to
acknowledge that the real grief she holds is the hurt of rejection, the
pain of loss and the desperate fear of never being able to love or be
loved again. With Amy's communication of love awakening in Felicia a
feeling and a hope for love, Felicia says, "I don't want it anymore." She
doesn't want it anymore- the hurt, the hatred, the three-way marriage,
the impossibility or unavailability of love. Felicia's confession in the light
of truth is not as explicit or complete as Amy's, but she has begun the
reversal, from hatred to love, from suffocating to breathing, from the
artificial light of deception to a genuine light of truth.
Amy's existential witness communicates not only her story but also
the incarnate expression of the reality and light of faith she lives. Amy,
who is apparently unwanted and unloved, yet whose name means the
loved one, enjoys an assurance since her solemn communication that
she is loved. This has been renewed in the forgiving love of
reconciliation and in her remembrance of these. It is Amy who, by her
assurance of being loved, is able to love Felicia in such a way as to
communicate to her the assurance that she too is loved. That
assurance is communicated through Amy's loving yet ultimately is found
also within Felicia's own being. A certain regard of love awakens within
the other person her own sense of divine filiation. (6)
Theater lets this communication of mystery touch our lives as well.
97
Notes to Chapter IV. Dot the I and Existential Witness to the Light of Truth
1. Gabriel Marcel, The Existential B ackground of Human Dignity,
Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1963, p.179.
2. Les points sur les I, Paris, Editions Grasset, 1936.
3. Dot the I, trans. By Katharine Rose Hanley in Two One Act
Plays by Gabriel Marcel: Dot the I and The Double Expertise,
University Press of America, Lanham, MD, 1986, pp. 1-21.
4. “Testimony and Existentialism” in The Philosophy of
Existentialism, Secaucus, NJ, Citadel Press, 1956, pp. 91-103.
5. “My Fundamental Purpose” (1937) in Présence and
Immortality, Pittsburgh, PA, Duquesne University Press, 1967,
pp.11-30.
6. “The Dangerous Situation of Ethical Values” in Homo Viator,
New York, Harper Torchbook, Harper & Bros., 1962, p.160.
98
Chapter V. The Rebellious Heart: and Human Creation
The Rebellious Heart is the title which Francis Lescoe insisted
Gabriel Marcel wanted for the English version (1974) of the play he
originally wrote in French with the title Le Coeur des autres (1921).(l)
The Rebellious Heart tells the story of Daniel Meyrieux'
s attempt to
achieve theatrical success as a playwright. The Rebellious Heart also
portrays the tragic parody Daniel creates as he fails to live a genuine
communion of love and creativity in his intimate family relations.
The setting for the play is the home of Daniel and Rose Meyrieux
in Paris in 1921. With them is Daniel’s natural son John, whom Rose
insisted that they adopt when the child'
s mother died. John has not been
told, however, that Daniel is his real father. The play presents the
struggles and conflicts that accompany Daniel Meyrieux's efforts to find
his identity through artistic creativity.
In the first act we see Daniel and Rose all caught up in efforts to
achieve theatrical success. Their preoccupation with critics' reviews
and their own reflections of what creativity involves have only two
interruptions. The first is the signal visit of Roses mother, Madame
Chambray, who comes to protest Daniels outrageous exploitation of
Aunt Solange'
s story and to request that Daniel withdraw the play or at
least delete those parts that are so personal that they really should
remain private. Daniel and Rose refuse this request. Although Rose
protests to her mother that she, Rose, is completely in accord with
what Daniel is doing, it seems that she does protest too much. She
has gradually increasing misgivings about the psychological
exploitation involved in Daniel'
s literary creations especially the play
Daniel is currently writing that capitalizes, obviously with artistic
embellishments, upon John'
s situation in their own household. The
second interruption occurs after Madame Chambley has left and Daniel is
back at work writing The Silent Child the play about which Rose is so
uncomfortable.
John returns from lunch at the home of a friend. When Rose
chides John for not congratulating his foster father on the success of
his play'
s premiere, John retorts that he doubts if anything can hurt his
father if it doesn'
t affect theatrical works. John then confides to Rose
that one of the maids has told him that Daniel is not merely his foster
father but is in fact his real father. On the heels of that stirring confidence
Daniel enters. He peremptorily dismisses John and proceeds to read
99
to Rose the dialogue that he has just written for his new play. It is the
scene wherein Gilbert, the silent child, reveals to his foster mother,
Thérèse, that he has learned that his so-called foster father is indeed
his real father. In that same scene Gilbert goes further and declares his
romantic feelings for Thérèse. Stunned, Rose can only listen. She
cannot even react.
In the second act Daniel is concerned only to find some way of
dealing with John so the latter doesn'
t think badly of him or pursue any
lines of embarrassing questioning. When father and son finally
converse, John asks Daniel why he has not acted as a real father
toward him, why he did not marry his mother. Why was he not kind and
caring toward John and his mother? John is revolted by Daniel's cruelty
and still holds fast to the sacredness of his mother'
s love. Daniel
summarily dismisses John'
s questions with the rejoinder that John is
simply too young to discuss or understand such issues. Daniel turns his
anger into blame that he transfers onto John for reading The Silent
Child without permission. John responds that he thought it a good way
to get to know his father, and he was right—it was a good way.
When Daniel tells Rose that John has read The Silent Child on
the sly, Rose ironically informs John that this action was like a breach
of trust. Alone with Rose, John confides that Daniel, by his heartless
dealings, has spoiled the only beautiful thing in his life, his relationship
with Rose. John reveals to Rose that he is disgusted by Gilbert in The
Silent Child, especially by the romantic feelings that Gilbert professes
for Thérèse. John, afraid lest others construe Gilberts feelings to be
John’s, distances himself from Rose while resenting the loss of the only
genuine affection left in his life.
At the end of the second act Daniel, on his own without consulting
either Rose or John, decides that John will start the following week as a
resident student at St. Louis Academy. Alone with Daniel, Rose feebly
warns him, "Take care."(2)
The third act of The Rebellious Heart shows the success that
Daniels dramatic works have won him. It also reveals the failure of his
intimate relations with his family.
The act opens with Daniel receiving accolades including even a
personal visit from an important critic, Paul Thomas. Daniel
reproaches Rose for not being more enthusiastic about this tribute to
100
his success. Rose, grieved by John'
s suffering, has become conscious
of what Daniel is doing. She protests what has become of their love.
There is no genuine communion. She finds she is no longer someone,
but rather has become merely a provider of tenderness and an
inspiration for plays. Daniel has completely eclipsed her. He has
annexed her. Since she doesn'
t count as a person, they no longer are
two but have become merely one. In her rebellion, Rose has now
identified with John'
s suffering and she asks Daniel to withdraw The
Silent Child. Moreover, she warns Daniel that if he refuses her request
she will leave him.
While Daniel goes off to deliver corrected proofs to his publisher,
Rose converses with John, who is home visiting after several months
away at boarding school. Rose is ready to leave Daniel in order to
mother John.
When Daniel returns from his publisher's, he seems anxious lest
Rose really think of leaving him. He is ready to make some minor
concessions in the future, although he reminds Rose that her situation
is most fortunate compared with that of other writers'
wives. Thereupon
he is content that they are reconciled. He embraces her and calls her
"his treasure." Rose, conscious of the tragic in their situation, resigns
herself to it hopelessly.
Rose (with the deepest sadness): Understand me, Daniel, I
am giving up myself; I know it. And I know also that I cannot
do otherwise. After ten years of our life, I am no longer
strong enough to think of myself. When a being has come to
this...go ahead, you are right. Take me. And when you are
short of subjects.... Final Curtain.(3)
The Rebellious Heart has a very sad ending. It ends, as it were, on
a muted note of despair. Rose'
s spirit is crushed. She has given up. It is
as if her soul has died, though she will continue to go through the
motions of life. John'
s life too already seems on the way toward tragic
ruin. He has given up any hope for genuine love or happiness in life. He
is ready, perhaps without even realizing it, to go the dissolute way of his
father. Daniel, by way of contrast, seems quite content with his life,
elated as he is by his recent theatrical success. He remains quite
insensitive to the tragic loss in the lives of those around him, the ravaging
of the lives of those closest to him--or as the French title, Le Coeur des
autres, “the heart of others” implies. The play has a tragic ending indeed. Comment [h1]: im
101
Marcel noted that The Rebellious Heart is a play with a most
somber ending. Still, he remarked that even those of his plays with
somber endings bring a certain light for the audience. It appears that
the quality of light that the ending of The Rebellious Heart brings is not
a direct light dawning explicitly in the consciousness of any of the lead
protagonists, but rather a diffuse light that is reflected, as it were, from
beyond them.(4)
This, like any other Marcel play, leaves us with questions. There are
first the questions affecting the characters of the play, questions that
even awaken among spectators certain feelings of rebellion or revolt.
For example, why is Daniel so insensitive to his wife and son? How can
he be so caught up in his theatrical success as to remain insensitive to
the toll that it has taken on the real lives of those closest to him? Why
does Rose dissolve and give up, abandoning all hope and any effort
toward achieving a genuine communion of love with Daniel or a better
life for John? Why doesn'
t Rose leave Daniel to care for John? The
prospects for life after the end of this play are bleak, in fact quite
hopeless. That is perhaps why the play leaves audiences with a deep
and lingering sadness. Gradually, however, the haunting quality of the
play gives rise to another level of questioning. On reflection spectators
begin to wonder about Daniel'
s success and creativity. One questions
whether Daniel's theater was genuinely creative or successful only for
its borrowings from the lives of real persons? It would be an awful
irony if what caused such suffering and loss in the lives of the people
close to him did not even contribute to his producing real art or
genuinely creative theater. Is it possible that Daniel failed to be
genuinely creative artistically as he failed to be creative and loving in
his family life?
Indeed, reflection on The Rebellious Heart invites us to
consider the question of what is genuine creation, both human and
artistic. The play also invites us to inquire what is required in order for
someone to be genuinely creative.
Marcel explored these questions both in his dramatic and his
philosophic works. For the remainder of this chapter we shall trace
how Marcel pursued his inquiry into these questions and brought to
light essential perspectives of insight, first through dramatic inquiry and
then through philosophic analysis. To retrace the development of
Marcel'
s thought on human creation, we shall refer to aspects of The
Rebellious Heart, which was written in 1919 and staged and then
102
published in Paris in 1921. We shall also refer to philosophic essays
written and published in France between 1932 and 1944, principally
several chapters in his book entitled Creative Fidelity, an English
translation of Du Refus à L’invocation, and also several chapters in his
book entitled Homo Viator, Introduction to a Metaphysic of Hope,
English translation of Homo Viator, prolégomenes à une métaphysique
de l’espéranoe. (5)
We find in The Rebellious Heart many comments that attempt to
clarify the nature of artistic creation. Patently, Daniel's efforts to
produce literary work that achieves theatrical success also illuminate to a
certain extent what artistic creation involves, although Daniel'
s life gives
us more of a reverse image of creativity than a direct illustration of what
genuine creation might involve. Theater presents the first moments of
inquiry.
Philosophy, as drawn from several chapters in Creative Fidelity and
Homo Viator, will guide a subsequent moment of tenacious reflection
with critically reasoned analysis of the nature of genuine creativity,
particularly as this can be manifest in the life of the artist and the parent.
Throughout the play we hear many comments that attempt to
clarify the nature of human creation. Clearly in the play creation
appears to involve taking a lived situation and adding something of
oneself and one'
s inspiration to it so as to make of it a new situation with
different people.(6) Throughout the play we hear various characters
trying to identify what artistic creation is. First John asks whether to
create is to make a medley of fact and fiction, the true and the false, the
real and the unreal, what is mine and what is someone else'
s, to fashion
from that something new. (II, 7, pp. 186-87)(7) And Rose wonders
whether to create is not to give over, to consecrate, what is sacred and
most precious in our lives.(I, 2, pp. 157-58; III, 3, p. 205)(8)
Finally, Daniel wonders whether to create doesn'
t mean to save,
to make eternal something of oneself because one has expressed it. (I,
1, pp. 149-50; I, 2, pp. 157-58)(9) Still, Rose'
s mother and John affirm
that people should not be sacrificed for the sake of art or ideas. What is
sacred in their lives should be held secret and should not be profaned
by distorting it for public display.(I, 2, pp. 153-58; II, 7, pp. 185-90)(10)
Throughout the play Daniel displays what appears upon reflection
to be a reverse image of creativity. Genuine creation involves a deeply
103
personal act. It is resourced at the spiritual center of the person whom it
expresses and engages. Daniel'
s efforts fall short of this. His artistic
inspiration is drawn not from the depth of his own being but from the
lives of others--Rose, John, Aunt Solange. He uses his literary talent to
embellish what was real and vital in the lives of others close to him. At
times he distorts, even warps, personal aspects of the private lives of
those close to him for their titillating or shocking effect.
In another respect too Daniel presents a reverse image of
genuine artistic creation. His efforts as a playwright find their direction
by seeking the approval of others, Paul Thomas, the public, or other
drama critics, instead of being guided by a profound urge or a strong
personal inspiration. Marcel warns that one can be misled if one takes
the direction of one'
s life or work from outsiders. One may even
become estranged from one's true source of inspiration, the depth of
oneself, and profane ones productivity, letting it become merely
compliance to the critics'
tastes and the public's expectations.(11)
In his philosophic reflections Marcel noted that genuine creations
arise from the depths of a person. Creativity springs from the spiritual
center of oneself. So for one to remain creative it is necessary to
maintain vital contact with what is alive in oneself and to resist the
temptation to profane oneself, thereby becoming alienated from ones
true self. One must instead remain simple and in touch with ones true
self, preserving a real intimacy of presence with oneself. For the center
of personhood, that particle of divine creation that reveals itself only to
love, is that depth of self that resources genuine creation.(12)
Marcel even maintains that it is finally only the artist who can truly
evaluate his or her creation. For only the artist can know whether he or
she has responded faithfully to a particular inner call. Only the author
can estimate the extent to which the creation measures up to,
corresponds to, or incarnates the original inspiration that gave rise to
the created work.(13)
Our reflections thus far enable us to see that human creation
involves taking something given, adding something of oneself and
thereby producing something new.(14) We also see that genuine
creation springs from the spiritual center of the person.(15) And we may
add, that the more creation flows from the very depth of who a person is,
the more that creation has the characteristics of freedom, spontaneity,
originality, and value.(16)
104
As we continue our consideration of Daniel'
s efforts toward
successful creativity and insights from Marcel'
s later philosophic
reflections that clarify these dramatic situations, we shall continue to
identify some of the requisite conditions for genuine human creativity.
As we consider Daniels efforts in human creation, we see that like
his attempts at artistic creation, while they may at first appear to be
successful, they reveal themselves upon reflection to be in fact failures.
Daniel, for his part, feels elated with his theatrical success and
equally content with the way he has "managed" his relations with those
closest to him. Yet the end of the play suggests the tragic failure that
characterizes the intimate family relations in the Meyrieux household.
Daniel’s failure as a father is clear both from reflection on the play
and from the perspectives of thought developed in the philosophic essay
"The Creative Vow as the Essence of Fatherhood."(17) Once again the
characters and situation of the play offer, as it were, a reverse image of
what genuine fatherhood or genuine human creation would involve, and
the philosophic analysis pursues further the question of what the
nature and possibility of genuine human creativity would involve.
While Daniel did beget a son, this happened as a mere biological
act. Daniels relationships were devoid of any of the characteristic
dimensions of genuine human creation. Daniel begot a child, but
although he had several opportunities to acknowledge John as his son,
that is "to be a real father" to him, Daniel declined or refused all of
these. Other than the biological act, Daniel denied any responsibility for
the creation of the child. Daniel did not acknowledge John as his son
and refused to marry or support John'
s mother. The decision to adopt
John into the Meyrieux family after the death of his mother was entirely
at the insistence of Rose, the foster mother. Daniel only went along
with it for Rose'
s sake, he himself never understanding why she wanted
such a situation. Even when John had been adopted, Daniel never
accepted or loved him, but rather belittled and distanced him,
sometimes in not too subtle ways. He just couldn'
t believe the genuine
affection that existed between Rose and John. Then when John
learned that Daniel was his natural father, Daniel thought only of
finding some way of reestablishing himself in the boy'
s esteem. When
challenged and confronted by embarrassing questions, Daniel
105
immediately exercised his parental authority by sending John away...to
boarding school.
Daniel patently fails in his human creativity or responsible parenting.
This appears to have occurred for lack of what Marcel called
"availability," a disposition or willingness to be there with and for another
and to care for the life of that other.(18)
Daniel appears as a rather shallow, egotistical, and self-absorbed
person. He showed himself incapable of the deep personal
commitment and the generosity of love that genuine fatherhood entails.
Marcel discovered personally and then disclosed through philosophic
reflection that the essence of human parenting is a creative vow. As he
clarified in "The Creative Vow as the Essence of Fatherhood,"
parenting is not a mere biological act, nor is it some casual or impersonal
gesture. It requires a deeply personal act of commitment. Parenting
involves a vow of commitment to be with and for another, guiding that
other through growth toward fulfillment in human personhood. Parenting
is a generous act of sharing life. The sharing is not casual or occasional
but should rather be generous and personally responsible. Human
creation springs from the conviction that life is a rich gift, and it
expresses a willingness to share that gift. The creative vow calls forth a
commitment to another to support that other in the adventure of life and
to offer one'
s guidance and inheritance toward the development of that
life.(19)
In other essays, "The Mystery of Family" and "The Ego and its
Relation to Others," Marcel points out that it is one'
s experience of a
family of origin that assures a child that he or she is the object of love and
careful attention, shareholder of a wealth in life that is to be developed so
that it can be received in turn by one'
s own children.(20)
To see the lack of hope that John has for any happiness in life is to
appreciate the extent to which Daniels parenting has failed. John,
rejected by his father, effectively makes his way unwittingly and
ironically to follow in his fathers own tragic footsteps.
Rose'
s rebellion against Daniel because of what is happening to
John and because of what has become of their marriage reveals the root
source of Daniels failure in human creativity. Daniel, it appears tragically,
is incapable of any genuine communion of other-directed love.
106
What Rose and Daniel have lived is a love of fusion. She has
enriched and has gradually been absorbed into his life. As Daniel said,
they are not two but one. Yet Rose realizes that this is finally not a
good thing because he has annexed her. She no longer counts as a
person. There is no longer any need to consult her wishes, to consider
her for herself, or to care for happiness in her life. Daniel'
s response is
merely to remind her that she is better treated than the wives of many
writers he knows so she ought to be thankful for that.(21)
What Rose desires is a genuine communion of love, wherein, as in
any genuine communion, the two are together in their difference.(22)
Or as Edith expressed it in another context in The Unfathomable,
“it is not his life, nor is it my life, it is our life.”(23) Rose seems to
aspire toward this genuine communion of love first for the sake of
John, so that his life not be sacrificed and merely used, but that he be
appreciated for his real worth, that Daniel recognize as Rose does that
John has real sensitivity and depth. Rose wishes and for a moment
insists that Daniel put aside his work and do something to protect their
son and to promote his happiness and well-being in life.
Daniel, for his part, is incapable of this kind of love. Or at least he
is unwilling now to consider Rose and John as others, people whose life
and happiness call for respectful care and the involvement of self-giving
love on the part of Daniel. Daniel either simply cannot hear or simply
refuses this call to love. Moreover, he takes Rose'
s son away from her.
Her heart is broken, so that finally and tragically she knows that their
union, which exalts Daniel, is neither happy nor fruitful.(24)
Marcel shows in the tragedy of The Rebellious Heart and further
clarifies through reflections in Creative Fidelity that genuine creativity is
resourced in a communion of love.
For Marcel creative fidelity is a requisite condition for any artistic or
human creation. Reflection on the mystery of human and artistic creation
reveals that creativity is rooted in fidelity. Ideally, creative fidelity is lived
as a communion of love. It involves a fidelity to oneself, a fidelity to
others, and a fidelity to an Absolute Other.(25)
In the essay "Obedience and Fidelity," in which Marcel showed
that genuine creativity requires a living fidelity to the spiritual depths of
oneself, he also explained that this fidelity to oneself seems almost
inseparable from a fidelity to another. For, paradoxically, one’s
107
fulfillment as a person develops through self-giving. And genuine
creativity is lived also as a response to a call. Thus a communion of love
is the ideal context in which human creation can occur.(26)
This situation is a far cry from the pitiable marriage that Rose
laments at the end of The Rebellious Heart. Creative fidelity is a
communion of love. Creative actions are realized as incarnate
gestures in response to the appeal of the loved one to whom one has
consecrated ones life. It is the actual presence of the beloved that invites
and inspires human creation. In a genuine communion of love, each
partner remains available to hear and willing to respond to the other's
appeal. It is through a permanent physical/spiritual presence that the
members of that community of love invite and inspire one anther'
s
creativity.(27)
The Rebellious Heart was staged and published in 1921. The
philosophic essays, "On the Ontological Mystery," "Obedience and
Fidelity," and "Creative Fidelity" appeared in 1932, 1940, and 1944. It
was over the course of twenty years that Marcel developed the notion of
creative fidelity, a central theme in his work and a leading idea in his life.
Marcel discovered this notion in an original manner. As he expressed it,
his life traveled one road, yet theater and philosophy depicted the
scenery on either side of the territory through which he traveled.(28)
Theater presents the concrete approach to the lived situation, and
philosophy offers a reflective analysis of the drama portrayed. Marcel also
maintained that theater often showed the tragic situations in life that
communicate an inclination toward despair, but that also brings another light
that opens onto mystery and hope.(29) Philosophy, through a process of
critical reflection, can then bring to light a positive identification of what
genuine human creation entails.(30)
The dual reflection shows the dangers and difficulties but also highlights
the positive value and possibility of an authentic creativity that calls for
freedom'
s choice of a way of living that draws on humanity'
s deepest resources
and makes the noblest uses of a person's potential. Still, it is theater that lets us
enter into the lived situation that enables us to follow the consciousness of the
tragic and opens onto the ontological mystery where we reach for our ultimate
recourse.(31) One finds in Marcel'
s thought the idea that in situations wherein
despair is a real temptation, there hope may appear in its intense
purity.(32) This is reminiscent of Alfred de Vigny'
s saying that our cries of
distress are often our most beautiful songs.
108
Marcel is convinced that only a most patient, probative, and also most
painful reflection can lead to the discovery of an Absolute that reveals itself as
our ultimate recourse and whose fidelity is the foundation of our own.(33)
For Marcel this Other, this Absolute Thou, becomes part of the integral reality
of our life and our creation.(34)
He sees human creation as a free and deeply personal act that is
rooted in fidelity; fidelity to oneself who lives fidelity to the other who inspires
and invites, and fidelity to an Other who enlivens, invites, inspires, and illumines
genuine creativity.(35)
109
Notes to Chapter V. The Rebellious Heart: and Human Creation
1. Le Coeur des autres, Paris, Grasset, 1921, pp. v-132. Play
premiered March 17, 1921 at the New Theater in Paris. The
Rebellious Heart in The Existential Drama of Gabriel Marcel, ed. F. J.
Lescoe, McAuley Institute, West Hartford, CT., 1974, pp. 145-215,
cf. p. 4.
2. The Rebellious Heart, Act II, Scene IX, p. 191.
3. Ibid., Act III, Scene VI, p. 215.
4. "The Drama of the Soul in Exile" in Three Plays by Gabriel Marcel:
A Man of God, Ariadne, The Votive Candle, New York, Hill and
Wang, 1965, p. 21.
5. Le Coeur des Autres, Paris, Grasset, 1921, pp. v-132; The
Rebellious Heart in The Existential Drama of Gabriel Marcel, ed. F. J.
Lescoe, McAuley Institute, West Hartford, CT., 1974, pp. 145-215.
Creative Fidelity, New York, Farrar, Straus and Company, 1964,
xxvi-261; Du Refus à L’Invocation, Paris, Gallimard, 1940, pp. 326;
Homo Viator Introduction to a Metaphysic of Hope, New York, Harper
and Bros., 1962, pp. 270; Homo Viator Prolégom‘enes à une
métaphysique de l'
espérance, Paris, Aubier, 1944, pp. iii-369.
6. "Testament philosophique" (Vienna, Sept. 1968) in La Revue de
Métaphysique et de Morale, tome 74, July-Sept., 1969, pp. 257,
258, 259. Reprinted in Présence de Gabriel Marcel, Cahier 4
Gabriel Marcel et les injustices de ce temps. La responsabilité du
philosophe, Paris, Aubier-Montaigne, 1983, pp. 1 7-37, cf. pp.
130-34.
7. The Rebellious Heart, Act II, Scene 7, pp. 186-87.
8. Ibid., Act I, Scene 2, pp. 157-58; Act III, Scene 3, p. 205.
9. Ibid., Act I, Scene 1, pp. 149-50; Act I, Scene 2, pp. 157-58.
10. Ibid., Act I, Scene 2, pp. 153-58; Act II, Scene 7, pp. 185-
90.
11. "Obedience and Fidelity" in Homo Viator, pp. 129-32.
110
12. Ibid., pp. 131-32.
13. Ibid., p. 130.
14. "
Testament philosophique," pp. 257, 258, 259.
15. "Obedience and Fidelity" in Homo Viator, pp. 131-32.
16. Ibid., pp. 129-34; "The Creative Vow as the Essence of
Fatherhood" in Homo Viator, pp. 105-106; "Observations on the
Notions of the Act and the Person," Ch. V, in Creative Fidelity, pp.
108-109.
17. "The Creative Vow as the Essence of Fatherhood" in Homo
Viator, pp. 98-124.
18. "Belonging and Disposability," Ch. II in Creative Fidelity, pp. 38-
57, esp. p. 53.
19. "The Creative Vow as the Essence of Fatherhood," in Homo
Viator, pp. 113-15.
20. "The Ego and its Relation to Others," in Homo Viator, pp.
13-28; "The Mystery of Family," in Homo Viator, pp.
68-97.
21. The Rebellious Heart, Act III, Scene 3, p. 204.
22. Introduction to Creative Fidelity, p. 8.
23. The Unfathomable in Presence and Immortality, Pittsburgh,
PA., Duquesne University Press, 1967, p. 280.
24. The Rebellious Heart, Act III, Scene VI, p. 215.
25. "Obedience and Fidelity," in Homo Viator, pp. 132-34.
26. Ibid., pp. 132-34; "The Ego and its Relation to Others," in Homo
Viator, pp. 22-23; "The Creative Vow as the Essence of
Fatherhood," in Homo Viator, pp. 104-106, 117-20.
27. "The Creative Vow as the Essence of Fatherhood," in Homo
111
Viator, pp. 117-20.
28. The Existential Background of Human Dignity, Cambridge, MA,
Harvard University Press, 1963, pp. 60-62; “An Essay in
Autobiography,” in The Philosophy of Existentialism, Secaucus, NJ,
Citadel Press, 1956, p. 128. "Gabriel Marcel: Le Paradoxe du
Philosophe-Dramaturge," Paris, no date, Alliance Française.
29. "Le Secret est dans les îles," in Le Secret est dans les îles,
Paris, Pion, 1967, p. 21-
30. L'
Heure théâtrale, de Giraudoux a J. P. Sartre, Paris, Plon,
1959, avant-propos, p. xi.
31. The Existential Background of Human Dignity, pp. 64-69; "Les
vrais problèmes de Rome n’est plus dans Rome," in Rome n’est
plus dans Rome, Paris, La Table Ronde, 1951, p. 162; "On the
Ontological Mystery," in The Philosophy of Existentialism,
Secaucus, N. J., Citadel Press, 1956, pp. 23, 26, 32.
32. "On the Ontological Mystery," in The Philosophy of
Existentialism, p. 32; "Sketch of a Phenomenology and a
Metaphysic of Hope" in Homo Viator, p. 36.
33. Préface to Le Seuil Invisible, Paris, Grasset, 1914, PP. 6-8; "On
the Ontological Mystery," pp. 23, 24, 32, 34, 38-39; "Sketch of a
Phenomenology and a Metaphysic of Hope," in Homo Viator, pp. 60-
63, 66-67.
34. "Meditations on the Idea of a Proof for the Existence of God,"
Ch. IX in Creative Fidelity, pp. 182-83.
35. "Creative Fidelity," Ch. VIII in Creative Fidelity, pp. 147-74;
"Meditations on the Idea of a Proof for the Existence of God," Ch.
IX in Creative Fidelity, pp. 175-83; "From Opinion to Faith", Ch. VI
in Creative Fidelity, pp. 120-39.
112
Chapter VI. The Double Expertise: Fidelity and Infidelity
The Double Expertise, a one-act comedy, portrays the tragicomic
situation that develops as Gilbert Marquiset, mustering all the help
he can, tries to find grounds for marrying his third wife. The setting is an
elegant bachelor apartment, Gilbert’s home in Paris, 1937. (1)
Since Gilbert’s mind muddles when he must decide on something
like marriage, he has invited his first wife, Georgette, to advise him.
Georgette'
s second husband, Stani Zürcher, accompanies her. Kate
Leliegeois, Gil'
s second wife, drops in unexpectedly. She has come to
claim something toward overdue alimony payments. She decides to
stay, feeling that she too should have the right to vote on Gil's
prospective bride-to-be.
When Miss Hedwig Frühling, Gilberts intended, arrives, she is
accompanied by her uncle, Mr. Edward Zürcher, an appraiser with a
double expertise. The conversation that ensues inquires about
Hedwig'
s likes and dislikes both for the sake of small talk and to
ascertain whether she is a suitable partner for Gil. Meanwhile Ed
Zürcher wanders around the apartment, inspecting its furnishings as
one might preview a gallery prior to an art auction or an antique sale.
Protesting against Zürcher'
s estimation of Gil'
s lack of taste,
Georgette and Kate reveal that each of them was married to Gil for a brief
time, Georgette for three years and Kate for fourteen months. On the
strength of that, Zürcher advises Hedwig to leave. To everyone'
s
.amazement, Hedwig, whose name means strife, remains and takes
charge. She proclaims an ultimatum. Either they all remain as a
harmonious group, or the others will have to leave and she will stay there
alone with Gil.
Noticing the familiar tone Stani uses with Zürcher, and learning
that they are father and son who became estranged over an inheritance
settlement, Hedwig announces that those two will go out onto the
balcony and settle their differences. Before that, however, there must
be a moment of "recollection." Hedwig announces the procedure they
will follow. Each is to listen in silence to his or her conscience and then
write his or her inspiration on a piece of paper.
113
Hedwig reads the statements aloud and comments on each one.
To Georgette and Stani'
s statement that they want to see prospectuses
on Hedwig'
s father'
s hotels, Hedwig exclaims triumphantly "There no
longer are any hotels. They were sold in order to found a commune to
regenerate life among those who can no longer live, nor work, nor
love."(2)
Georgette and Stani'
s reaction to that news is clear-cut. No
hotels, no marriage contract. As Georgette and Stani leave, they shake
Gil's hand as one might at graveside after a funeral ceremony. Kate, for
her part, takes a Dufy painting to cover back alimony payments.
Zürcher drifts out, babbling about how this experience has aged him
ten years.
Hedwig and Gil are alone. Hedwig coos enthusiastically to Gil.
"You'
ll see, we’ll lead a very restful life ...green vegetables
...fresh air,...long walks ...soothing naps.... Gradually you'
ll learn to live
a natural healthy life." Gil, dumbfounded, groans his response, "a life
that restful, I'
m afraid it might kill me."(3)
The Double Expertise is an artful, cleverly written comedy. It is
amusing in many ways, yet it also has a disquieting effect. Marcel referred
to his comedy as a "yes...but" part of his work. It is precisely this
unsettling aspect of the play that we will investigate.
On an obvious level, the play is a satirical farce. Its theme of
matchmaking with family and friends assisting fits comfortably into
the tradition of situational comedies. Comic characters are caught up in
the ridiculous task of trying to find grounds for matrimony where patently
none seem to exist. There is, moreover, the comic device of concealed
identities becoming revealed and overlapping relationships becoming
embarrassingly clear. There is also the parody of caricatures. As the
identities of the jury--Gil, Georgette, Stani, and Kate--and the appraiser--
Ed Zürcher--are disclosed, it becomes clear that they in no way have
qualities of expertise that would inspire confidence in their abilities to
evaluate grounds for matrimony, advise about good relationships, or
guide harmonious living. There is furthermore the farcical, almost
slapstick, ending as the hope for a good match fizzles and the
gathering breaks up. The others leave in a surprising reversal of the
movement toward a merger that characterized the direction of the play
up to that point. Finally, there is the ironic and dissonant note as Gil and
Hedwig find themselves alone together. Hedwig proclaims what an
114
idyllic life they'
ll lead, and Gil responds that a life that restful could kill
him.
The Double Expertise is a clever and amusing farce. Upon
reflection, however, we can notice that there is a shadow side to the
whole play that has a haunting effect. At the play's end, it is apparent
that the matchmaking has failed. Hedwig and Gilbert appear ill-suited,
and as appraiser and jury leave, the verdict seems to read "no deal."
Still there is a melancholic note of nostalgia. For Gilbert needs a wife,
someone to care for him, and Hedwig needs someone to take care of.
Clearly Gil needs to learn to live, to love, and to work, and Hedwig is all
ready to rehabilitate him. The prospects seem vain. Yes...but.
Perhaps it could work. It is unlikely, yet there is a trace of
disappointment. So the play ends on a disconcerting note. There is a
similar feeling of inadequacy about the appraiser'
s and the jury'
s attempts
to evaluate. When appraiser and jury agree, no deal; there still
remains a concern or dissatisfaction about their attempt to find criteria
by which to evaluate. Thus a deeper question is unearthed, one that
begins to surface and haunt us. Are there grounds that can motivate a
choice and substantiate a prediction for a happy, stable marriage? If
not, then are the serial marriages of Gilbert, Georgette, Stani, and
perhaps Hedwig, or the marred and broken relationships lived by
Kate and Mr. Ed Zürcher the only fate left? If so, that is a sad fate, a
disappointingly narrow set of options, an unsettling prospect for those
who might still hope for something more stable in human and familial
relationships.
Clearly the play gives rise to questions in the minds of its audience.
As Marcel observed the last scene of a play is most important both for
the unity it brings to the play as a whole and for the questions it raises in
the minds of the spectators.(4) Certainly the final scene of The Double
Expertise raises the question of whether or not Gil and Hedwig will
marry. With that it reopens at a deeper level a whole series of
questions about whether or not there are grounds for marriage. The
end of the play leaves us with these questions and invites us to reflect
on our own and consider whether or not there are grounds for
matrimony and criteria that would enable us to foresee whether there
are grounds for a solid marriage that might last.
The way we will proceed in our consideration of these questions is
first to trace how they are defined in the dramatic action of The Double
Expertise and then explore the clarification that critical reflection can
115
bring to these questions as Marcel discusses them in "Obedience and
Fidelity" and in chapters II, VIII, and IX of Creative Fidelity. (5)
Characters in the play illustrate different attitudes and stances
that can be adopted on the issue of criteria for matrimony and for a
good and lasting marriage. They bring to light the various
interpretations these standpoints suggest. They also occasionally
disclose some of the presuppositions of these various stances and
attitudes. The characters and action of the play further bring to light
certain avenues of investigation that seem worth exploring. In this way
The Double Expertise not only raises questions, it brings them more
clearly into focus and thus prepares the task of reflective clarification.
The question of marital criteria runs throughout the entire play. It is
clarified and explored but left unanswered. It is up to the audience to
critically clarify and personally resolve the issues raised. Right from the
start, Georgette and Gilbert compare their successive domestic
economies, noting advantages and disadvantages of frugal versus
prodigal, calm versus agitated, stable versus changing. Then
Georgette and Stani try to help Gil recognize his own estimation of this
latest prospect. Is she pretty? Does she suit you? Is she modest, or old
fashioned? Is she a nurse? Will she be a good companion for Gil in his
old age? In response to a query from Stani, Georgette remarks that
marrying is like buying an apartment or even a house. It'
s quite a
permanent arrangement. When Stani retorts that it can always be
resold, Georgette admits that that is true, but sold at a loss, so one keeps
it.
À propos of Gil's second marriage, with Kate, Georgette affirms
that this was merely a parenthetical break. It'
s as Doctor ZürcherSolomon
says--each person has one serious illness, emotional as well as
physical, in his or her lifetime. Gil'
s marriage to Kate really was a bad
precedent. One really shouldn'
t go against one'
s deepest feelings. What
matters now is to get Gil nicely settled.
À propos of households, finances, and living arrangements, Gil
blurts out that Hedwig'
s father owns three big hotels in Engadine,
Switzerland. Stani and Georgette agree that Gil should ask to see the
prospectuses on these hotels. No need to be embarrassed, just say that
a friend is considering vacationing in that area.
116
With Kate'
s arrival on the scene, the importance of financial status
in marriage contracts becomes evident. Kate comes to claim
something from Gil'
s apartment as security for late alimony payments.
The others really wonder what Kate lives on; her phone has already
been disconnected. Both Gil and Stani admit they are financially
embarrassed, temporarily a bit short. Georgette has money, and Kate is
very nearly bankrupt. Obviously Gil's need for a financially
advantageous marriage is capital. The bride-to-be must offer him
financial security.
When Miss Hedwig Frühling and her uncle Mr. Edward Zürcher visit,
the ensuing conversation seeks out traits of compatibility and
incompatibility. Preferences in life-style vary widely. Personality
differences are also significant. Hedwig is a naturalist. Health foods,
wildflowers, and the high Alps suit her tastes. She unabashedly states
her dislike for cities and for modern art in which nothing is
recognizable. She concedes that if one must live in a city one can
adjust. Fortunately, however, there are the weekends when ore can get
out into the country for long walks. On the strength of her own say-so
she is very much the doctor and the person in charge. Gil is quite the
opposite. He is a city sophisticate. Long walks tire him. The mere
prospect of them discourages him. He'
s also apparently stunned by
this enthusiasm for wildlife and nature that the Swiss Miss is exuding.
Uncle Ed, who is not only Hedwig'
s escort but also an appraiser,
inspects the furnishings of Gil'
s apartment and his impression is quite
negative. He judges there’s not much money or class there and so
concludes that Gil is not an interesting prospect.
If experience were a criterion for good matches and lasting
marriages, Gil might qualify as an expert, since he'
s been married
twice… Apparently, however, something more than experience, such
as wisdom, art, or prudence, is needed to produce good judgments.
Gil has lots of experience, but as Georgette stated, "Gil appears very
observant without actually being so."(6) If it comes to making a decision
or a well-founded choice, Gil is lost. His mind muddles and he loses his
bearings.
Hedwig, who has the least marital experience, is surest of her
judgment. She wants to marry. Gil is available. So that makes him
eligible. Despite evidence to the contrary, Hedwig hopes for the best.
She has complete self-confidence. She looks forward to the marriage
and feels sure that it will succeed. The success she envisions, however,
117
involves Gil being transformed to her wishes and desires. He needs to
relearn how to live, to love, and to work. They'
ll proceed gradually. Gil
will adjust, even come to enjoy it. After all, as she says, "she's the
doctor." Her criteria are her self-confidence and her tenacious desire
that things be the way she wants them to be.
Hedwig proposes a method of "recollection" --that is silent listening to
ones own conscience--as a means for discerning and decision-making.
In the context of the play, however, this procedure is hardly taken
seriously. What we see is superficial and not taken seriously; it
becomes a mere parody rather than an authentic exercise of genuine
recollection.
Throughout the play, jury and appraiser alike seek by various criteria to
estimate whether the proposed match between Hedwig and Gil would
be a good and lasting one. A variety of criteria are brought to light. The
relevance of taste, life-style preference, harmony or complementarity of
personality, financial status, deep feelings, experience, appraiser's
expertise, even "recollection" for discernment were all considered. Yet
these criteria did not reach a conclusion in the case of Hedwig and Gil.
The fact that the play ends with every indication that a marriage
will not take place, but without assuring that conclusion, raises the
question of whether or not the criteria considered by jury and appraiser
are adequate. The disconcerting ending to the play seems to raise the
question whether grounds for a decision to marry and grounds for a
stable and lasting marriage are not of a distinctively different sort. We
begin to glimpse that if a marriage occurs, this happens as a result of an
interpersonal dialogue that creates a commitment by mutual and
reciprocal consent. A decision to marry one another is a free choice
created in interpersonal dialogue. If reasons conclude or if criteria
compute, is this not finally because of a personal element of free
choice that intervenes? Is it not the case that no matter how an
evaluation process is calculated and tallied, what really counts is that
personal element of whim, preference, or commitment that determines
what the free choice will be?
As the play ends, who knows if Hedwig and Gil will marry or
not? The choice will be determined by their decision or their lack of
decision. Ultimately, it is Hedwig and Gil themselves who will create
their decision to part company, or to marry or perhaps even to love
one another, as unlikely as that may at first appear.(7)
118
The criteria that surfaced in the play are certainly valid indicators of
various kinds of compatibility. Yet these kinds of compatibility are not
adequate grounds for matrimony. If marriages are based on these
kinds of affinities then the relationships cease to exist when the
compatibility is no longer there. Since any and everyone can change
regarding the various criteria highlighted in the play, no commitment
would be stable if based only on affinities of this sort.
Grounds for matrimony are drawn from a whole different order,
namely the distinctively interpersonal order of love, freedom,
commitment, and intersubjective communion. Marcel clarifies this point
prior to investigating the nature of genuine interpersonal commitments
and the possibility of living interpersonal relations with creative fidelity.
When Marcel does investigate these issues philosophically, the questions
he raises are even deeper and more difficult than those raised by the play,
for it is in the context of human freedom's authenticity that Marcel
inquires about the possibility of interpersonal commitments and the
possibility of living out these commitments as creative fidelity.(8)
Marcel'
s philosophic analysis brings into focus the following
questions. He inquires whether interpersonal ground for a deep and
lasting commitment to marriage can be found. He also seeks to clarify
what the nature of such an interpersonal commitment might be.
Articulating his questions with reference to human freedom, Marcel
wonders how both freedom and fidelity can be preserved within the
context of a marriage commitment. Specifically he inquires as to how
freedom can commit itself without enslaving the person so committed?
He also asks explicitly how one can reasonably commit oneself to love
another in the future when circumstances, one's own feelings, and the
other person may have changed. For one might be left merely living out
routine compliance, fulfilling a promise begrudgingly and not loving
genuinely or wholeheartedly. Marcel inquires as to the manner and the
conditions in which one can voice a commitment to a lasting
interpersonal relationship. He likewise explores how one can live out
creative fidelity to such a commitment in a manner that is genuinely
faithful and at the same time respectful of freedom and human dignity?
Marcel explores the questions raised by The Double Expertise
philosophically in several essays, especially "Obedience and Fidelity" in
Homo Viator and chapters of the book entitled in English Creative
Fidelity. (9)
119
When Marcel considers the possibility of a marriage or of any
lasting interpersonal commitment, he raises several questions that are
intellectually exacting and personally demanding. Can one responsibly
commit one's freedom? Has one the right to bind one'
s freedom in a
lasting way to love and be faithful to another person? Does one have the
right to engage ones liberty for the future, when circumstances, others,
even ones own feelings may have changed? It is these questions that
we shall examine in the context of Gabriel Marcel's reflective
clarifications of intersubjectivity.
Can one responsibly bind ones freedom, committing oneself to
love another with a steadfast love in the future? Certainly one cannot
responsibly abdicate freedom, getting rid of responsibility for the use of
one's freedom by disposing of that responsibility into the hands of
another. Freedom cannot be bound or given away. Nor can freedom be
committed to demeaning or enslaving causes without falling beneath
the level of human dignity.(10) One cannot responsibly give one's
freedom away, but one can validly commit one's freedom, definitively
claiming responsibility for that lasting will. One can commit one's
freedom responsibly, knowing that one continues to have authorship
and responsibility for that commitment. One can commit one'
s freedom
authentically when one recognizes that to commit oneself to this cause
or person is enobling and is in fact the best use one can make of one's
freedom.(11) Only conscious, responsible commitment is worthy of
human freedom.
A commitment then that binds people in an interpersonal
relationship would have to be made as a mutual agreement of two
liberties to be worthy of these people's dignity. Such a commitment
should also evolve through a dialogue of freedoms. We will see shortly
a sketch of how this commitment can occur.
Still on the side of freedom Marcel pursues the question of
whether or not one can validly engage oneself to love another in the
future. Would not such a commitment involve a risk of compromising the
genuineness of love and the self-determination of freedom? Would not
such a situation also introduce the possibility of hypocrisy, since one can
easily imagine changes in circumstances and even in character that
could cause one to regret the commitment and comply with its demands
only in a begrudging way.(12) If a bond were founded only on feelings,
circumstances, and compatibilities that can readily change, or even if the
120
relationship were founded on a pledge of freedom that reserved its right to
renege, then the commitment would not last if any of these factors
changed. Certainly some of the basic factors will alter, and it is all the
more likely that a relationship will not last when the commitment is
envisioned as being essentially only a conditional one. So Marcel has
set forth the challenge to think about how freedom can commit itself
without denaturing itself. He further asks, once a pledge is made, how
it can be lived out in a manner respectful of freedom'
s essential selfdetermination.
Marcel'
s approach to this type of question is usually to reflect
critically, exploring various concrete situations until he finds the
subjective attitudes that are requisite for certain events or relationships to
become possible.
For a valid interpersonal commitment to occur, or even to be
possible, several conditions are requisite. The first requisite condition is
that there be two persons involved, not just two individuals but rather
two persons. What does Marcel mean by that distinction? A person is
someone who is available. In order to be capable of self-disposition,
one must first have a certain degree of self-possession. A person is one
who knows what he or she loves and lives for.
In chapter II of Creative Fidelity on "Belonging andDisposability"
Marcel offers a lengthy excursus on belonging.(13) The person who
recognizes what he or she wants to be is someone who belongs to
himself or herself and who is capable of self-gift. By contrast, someone
who does not belong to himself or herself cannot give himself or
herself. It follows that the one who says, "I belong to no one, to no
cause, I belong only to myself," errs. If one belongs to no one, he does
not belong to himself or to anything. As a matter of fact, it is an
anarchy beneath the level of liberty to try and maintain that one does
not want to devote oneself to any cause, value, or person. Such a
person is committed to nothing, consecrated to nothing. Such an
individual cannot promise his allegiance or fidelity from one minute to the
next. Someone like that pretends to belong to himself or herself alone,
but actually he or she belongs to no one, is committed to nothing. By
contrast, an authentic person is capable of commitment, devotedness,
consecration, self-gift, in brief: love. Such a person knows what he or
she loves and lives for. Because of belonging and disposability, such a
person has something to give in response to the appeal of another
121
person. We meet here a paradox. To possess oneself is to be capable
of giving oneself.(14)
There can be no commitment or self-gift between individuals who
do not possess themselves. Availability and belonging are capabilities
only of persons who possess themselves, determine and know what
they love and live for. The unavailable individual has not determined
what he or she values and belongs to, and so that individual is incapable
of self-gift. Such an individual is unavailable, incapable of consecrating,
giving, or committing himself or herself. All the more so the unavailable
individual is incapable of pledging or premising faithfulness in love, now
or in the future.
Gilbert is a fine example of someone who does not know who he
is or what he wants out of life. He never can decide. He hasn'
t
determined what he loves and lives for, so he hasn'
t enough selfpossession
to be capable of self-disposition. He may appear selfcentered
in his instinct for survival. Still he is not conscious and
resolved, or self-possessed enough to be capable of a commitment.
Likewise, he is not self-possessed enough to welcome or assume
responsibility for another.
Hedwig displays another kind of unavailability. She knows what
she wants and is overly determined to get it. She wants the marriage
with Gil. She desires it tenaciously. Yet she is unavailable in the sense
that she is not disposed to welcome others, be receptive to them, or let
them be as they are. She is not open to accepting Gil as he is. Instead
she is committed only to what Gil will be when he has relearned to live,
to work, and to love—under the tutelage of Dr. Frühling, of course.
Hedwig doesn'
t give the impression that she is capable of receptivity, or
that she can love and accept another as he or she is. She is so filled with
her own plans that she has no room to w e l c o m e another with that
other’s particular individuality and life projects. To be available, or to be
capable of belonging, is to be open and receptive to the Présence of the
other person. Once again we see a paradox. Giving oneself entails
receiving others. (15)
Looking at Gil and Hedwig'
s situation from the perspectives that
philosophic analysis brings to light, we can begin to understand why
the play doesn'
t disclose grounds for marriage. Such grounds need to
be of an interpersonal sort, and neither Hedwig nor Gil, where they are
in the action of the play, seems to show signs of the requisite attitudes
122
necessary in order for a genuine interpersonal relationship to occur.
For an intersubjective relationship to occur, there must be two
persons with knowledge and self-determination of who they are and what
they live for, two persons capable of availability or disposability and
belonging, two persons capable of an act that commits their freedoms
and that also creates and confirms their resolve to be loving and
available for one another. When these conditions are provided, then an
interpersonal relationship can be created by a dialogue of freedoms.
First there is an appeal, concretely expressed, of one person inviting the
other to be with and for him or her. Then there is the other's response.
It may be yes, no, maybe, no way, later, etc. If the response is
affirmative, then the I-Thou encounter occurs, a spiritual bond is created
by the reciprocal self-gift of two persons. The spiritual exchange of that
reciprocal self-gift to be with and for one another is what authors the IThou
encounter and constitutes an I-Thou relationship.(16)
An I-Thou relationship is a spiritual exchange of persons willing to
be with and for one another. Normally an I-Thou encounter grows into a
stable interpersonal relationship of love and friendship. Furthermore, this
interpersonal relationship can develop to constitute a veritable co-esse, a
stable communion of intersubjectivity, or an interpersonal bond of love.
The logic of love wants a relationship to be permanent. As Marcel
wrote, “To say to someone, '
I love you' is to say to that person, '
You...you will not die.” “To love someone is to want that person to be
and to be a Présence for me.”(17)
How can one promise love that is lasting? Obviously such a
commitment can only be made under certain exacting conditions and with
the noblest of human attitudes.(18) What are the requisite conditions?
And how can a lasting commitment be validly founded? As we said
earlier, a commitment requires two persons who know what they want
from life. It is also requisite that these two persons be sufficiently
transparent to reveal themselves to one another. It is likewise
necessary that they be sufficiently respectful of one another to invite and
grant disclosure to one another of who they are and what they live for
as their relationship grows and meets the challenges of change. Those
who propose to commit themselves to one another know what they
love and live for. They also know that with all their being at their
disposal, it is their will to promote the essentials of life with and for one
another. Moreover, they also know that both of them wholeheartedly will
to live out their commitment to love one another in the future. And so a
123
vow is made. They consecrate themselves to live with and for one
another.
The vow to love one another in a lasting way can indeed be well
founded, even if in some respects it partakes of the nature of hope in that
it refers to the future that has not yet come to be and so is not yet fully
determined, and also in the respect that it recognizes that its grounds
of assurance are interpersonal. Marcel points out that one should never
underestimate the determination and strength that one receives toward
living out one's promises from the very fact that one resolves to remain
faithful.
The fact is that when I commit myself, I grant in principle
that the commitment will not again be put in question. And
it is clear that this active volition not to question something
again intervenes as an essential element in the
determination of what in fact will be the case....My
behaviour will be completely colored by this act embodying
the decision that the commitment will not again be
questioned. The possibility which has been barred or denied
will thus be demoted to the rank of a temptation.(19)
Some view the future as if it were an event that happens to us
without our being in any way able to influence its significance. Such an
attitude looks at one'
s pledge from the outside as would a distant
spectator. (20) Yet such distancing from ones act can be the beginning
of ones disowning it. In fact this attitude entails, whether consciously or
not, the betrayal of a mystery that one is part of and reduces that
mystery to the status of a problem from which one is disengaged.(21)
By contrast, it is possible to see that one'
s attitude and resolve now can
greatly influence ones future stance and choices. So what is capitally
important is to recognize that once one'
s troth is pledged, once one'
s
life is committed, then one considers as a temptation to betrayal any
inclination toward infidelity that might occur. The sense of freedom'
s
living in love is to refresh and renew this commitment of love, to
complete it and to enjoy fulfilling it. Any idea of abandoning this
commitment or bondl of love appears as a betrayal of one's beloved,
oneself, and one'
s life and not in some distorted way as a chance for a
new life or a second career. Marcel even goes so far as to ask whether
one may not pledge as part of one's original commitment the intention
that, even if on some level one'
s feelings alter, one'
s behavior would
nonetheless remain consistent with one'
s original commitment. Marcel
124
observes that in certain instances this can even be a higher form of
fidelity.(22)
Marcel observes that the vow of interpersonal commitment is
sacred, essentially because it springs from freedom. It is I myself who
create it, will it, pledge it, offer it as a gift to another person. The more
the act is free, the more it is personal, that is, acknowledged by its
author.(23) The vow is also sacred because it is addressed to another
person whom it engages and affects. The more I realize that the other
is incapable of exacting compliance and is in fact powerless against me if
I should forsake my pledge, the more I see the other as vulnerable and
recognize the sacredness of the trust for which I am responsible.
Furthermore, the more the act is free, the more it becomes an act of
self-giving love, not a selfish act of covetous desire that seeks
principally the advantages the other may provide.(24)
It is finally significant that the vow is spoken as an act of hope that
is also the beginning of a prayer. "May it be given to us to find the
means to remain faithful to the love we now vow."(25)
A vow of unconditional and permanent love is a vow that strives to
be absolute. It thus anticipates and calls upon the help of an Absolute
Thou as the ultimate source of our strength and hope. As Marcel wrote
in Homo Viator, the statement of hope in its ultimate purity and intensity
is "I hope in Thee for us."(26)
As Marcel sees interpersonal relations evolve, they develop
through dialogue and growing engagement of freedoms whereby
persons commit themselves more and more to be fully and permanently
with and for one another. The relationship is initiated through a dialogue
of freedoms: appeal, response, and gratuitous conferral of presence.
This reciprocal agreement constitutes an I-Thou encounter. If an
interpersonal relationship develops, the spiritual exchange of Présence
and availability increases. If friendship, marriage, or religious
commitment evolves, it comes to the point of commitment that Marcel
describes as "belonging."
In chapter two of Creative Fidelity, "Belonging and Disposability,"
Marcel inquires as to what can it mean to use the term "belonging," not in
the context of things, but in the context of intersubjectivity? To say "you
belong to me" certainly does not mean that you belong to me like a
slave or a bicycle. To say "you belong to me," means that I take to
125
heart everything that affects you and your well-being, as affecting me.
To say "I belong to you" rejects any connotation of possession or
abdication of autonomy. It affirms that all I am and have is at your
disposal. There is a trust fund in your account that you can draw on in
support of your hopes and projects.(27)
It is this sense of belonging and assured availability that is
affirmed in a commitment of love--in friendship, marriage, or religious
promises. A pledge of commitment formalizes the belonging, it
actualizes the commitment of freedom in an explicit way and clarifies the
nature of the relationship and the legitimate expectations it includes. A
commitment of matrimony aspires to be a total and complete selfgiving.
The intimacy, depth, and completeness of that reciprocal selfgift
calls for a commitment that is interpersonal and lasting. And the
living out of a lasting commitment of belonging in an authentic fashion is
what Marcel calls "creative fidelity."
Marcel reflects on how it is possible to live fidelity in a manner that
is respectful of the dignity of freedom and also of the exigencies of
genuine communion of love. The following discussion clarifies the
authentic manner of living creative fidelity. The description also clarifies
an authentic manner of founding a vow of marriage as an interpersonal
commitment.
Marcel purifies our understanding through a negative clarification.
Creative fidelity is not merely certain forms of conformity or unswerving
compliance. Creative fidelity is the willingness to invoke the actual
Présence of the beloved and to expect in relation to gratuitously
conferred renewals of the actual presence of that loved one, an
incitement to create, that is to love faithfully in new and fresh ways.
So Marcel clarifies. Creative fidelity is not merely keeping ones
promises no matter what, even though it is good to keep one'
s
promises. Nor is creative fidelity merely a question of fulfilling
contractual obligations one has agreed to, though it is good to be true
to ones word. These forms of compliance can become impersonal,
mechanical, routine observances. They can also become merely
annoying demands to which one responds grudgingly and finally with
bitterness and resentment. Fidelity is not simply a question of
constancy in one'
s behavior or consistency in complying one'
s behavior
to one'
s principles or promises, or one'
s reputation or popular image.
126
Nor is creative fidelity a simple compliance to what one believes others
expect of him or her.(28)
Marcel points out that it is difficult to ascertain to what or to whom
one is faithful. It is difficult to discern whether fidelity is lived first as
faithfulness to oneself, or faithfulness to another. It is likely that
normally one lives faithfulness to the other in the appeal he or she is
and to oneself in the response that one is to that invitation, and in the
joy that one has to be a response of creative fidelity to that call to
be.(29)
Fidelity is certainly not merely repeating certain words or gestures.
Nor is it merely a question of obeying orders, observing laws, and
following rules. In the essay, "Obedience and Fidelity," Marcel notes
that obedience may be commanded by a chief or officer with authority to
direct certain functions, but fidelity cannot be ordered merely by dint of
office or authority. Fidelity must be merited, and it is addressed to a
person, not an office, idol, or role.(30)
Actually the form of fidelity that is authentic and well founded, that
form of fidelity that can renew itself and remain creative, is a fidelity that
invokes the actual presence of the other person. Conferred gratuitously,
it is the presence of the other person that incites love and inspires
incarnate gestures expressing love, that is, acts of creative fidelity.
The renewals of presence that refresh love and fidelity are also acts
of intersubjectivity. Marcel notes in his essay "On the Ontological
Mystery" that it depends upon me to invoke presence, to remain open,
receptive, permeable. But in point of fact it does not depend totally on
me to summon it forth. When presence is renewed, its revelation, a
correlate to invocation, manifests itself inevitably as a gift, and always
brings an inspiration to create. Presence always has its characteristic
traits of gratuity, altereity, and incitement to create.(31)
This positive sketch of the nature of an authentic interpersonal
commitment and a life of creative fidelity that we have drawn from
Marcel'
s philosophic reflections goes far beyond what we might have
imagined from the options depicted in the tragic comic farce The Double
Expertise. In this instance again we see that theater and philosophy
complement one another remarkably for those willing to reflect on
existential issues that affect our lives.
127
After both dramatic and philosophic reflections we can see that an
adequate, although by no means automatic, foundation for an
interpersonal commitment and a lifetime of intersubjective communion
requires the following attitudes and subjective dispositions:
1) That one is capable of self-possession and self-disposition.
2) That both persons recognize one another as willing the
same essentials for life, and as being willing to share and
provide these essentials of life for one another and
eventually forr others too.
3) That the interpersonal commitment to be with and for one
another for life is coauthored by a dialogue of freedoms,
thus co-constituting a spiritual exchange that becomes a
communion of intersubjectivity, a veritable co-esse.
4) That people express this mutual and reciprocal self-gift in a
resolve of freedoms that expresses itself as a vow that
includes a note of hope and a tone of prayer.
5) That people renew this spiritual exchange by acts of
presence one to another, as privileged and tangible
moments of the intersubjective communion that founds and
renews their life of creative fidelity.
128
Notes to Chapter VI. The Double Expertise: Fidelity and Infidelity
1. La Double Expertise in Théâtre comique, Paris, Albin Michel, 1947;
Two One Act Plays by Gabriel Marcel: Dot the I and The Double
Expertise, Lanham, Maryland, University Press of America, 1986, pp.
23-38.
2. The Double Expertise, Act I, Scene 3, p. 37.
3. Ibid, p. 38.
4. "Drama of the Soul in Exile," in Three Plays by Gabriel Marcel,
New York, Hill and Wang, 1965, p. 30; Le Secret est dans les îles,
Paris, Plon, Préface, pp. 12, 20-21.
5. Creative Fidelity, New York, Farrar, Straus and Co., Ch. II., "Belonging
and Disposability," pp. 38-57; Ch. V, "Observations on the Notion
of the Act and the Person," pp. 104-19; Ch. VIII, "Creative Fidelity,"
pp. 147-74; Ch. IX, "Meditations on the Idea of a Proof for the
Existence of God," pp. 175-83. Homo Viator An Introduction to a
Metaphysic of Hope, New York, Harper Bros., 1962, Chicago,
Henry Regnery Co., 1952, "Obedience and Fidelity," pp. 125-34.
6. The Double Expertise, Act I, Scene 1, p. 28.
7. L'
Heure théâtrale, Paris, Plon, 1959, avant-propos, p. iv.
8. Creative Fidelity, Ch. I, "Incarnate Being as the Central Datum
of Metaphysical Reflection," pp. 26, 30; Ch. II, "Belonging and
Disposability," pp. 147-74; Homo Viator, "Obedience and
Fidelity," pp. 125-34.
9. Cf. note 5 above.
10. "Obedience and Fidelity," p. 129.
11. Creative Fidelity, Ch. II, "Belonging and Disposability," pp. 47-
49.
12. Ibid., Ch. VIII, "Creative Fidelity," pp. 153-64.
13. Ibid., Ch. II, "Belonging and Disposability," pp. 38-47.
129
14. Ibid., "Belonging and Disposability," pp. 51-55; Homo Viator; "The
Ego and its Relation to Others," pp. 13-28; The Philosophy of
Existentialism, Secaucus, New Jersey, Citadel Press, 1956, "On
the Ontological Mystery," pp. 24-25.
15. Creative Fidelity, Ch. II, "Incarnate Being as the Central Datum of
Metaphysical Reflection," pp. 27-29.
16. Ibid., pp. 32-34; "On the Ontological Mystery," p. 39.
17. Trois Pièces, Le Regard Neuf, Le Mort de demain, La Chapelle
ardente, (Three Plays, The New Look, Tomorrow'
s Dead, The
Votive Candle), Paris, Plon, 1931, Le Mort de demain (Tomorrow'
s
Dead), Act II, Scene 6, p. 161; cited by Joseph Chenu, Le Théâtre
de Gabriel Marcel et sa signification métaphysique, Paris, Aubier,
1948, p. 97.
18. Creative Fidelity, Ch. VIII, "Creative Fidelity," pp. 157-59, 160-62.
19. Ibid., p. 162.
20. Ibid., Ch. I, "Incarnate Being as the Central Datum of
Metaphysical Reflection," p. 31.
21. Ibid., Ch. VIII, "Creative Fidelity," pp. 163-64; "On the Ontological
Mystery," pp. 28-30, 35.
22. Ibid., Ch. VIII, "Creative Fidelity," p. 158.
23. Ibid., Ch. V, "Observations on the Notions of the Act and the
Person," pp. 107-109, 113; "Obedience and Fidelity," pp. 132-33.
24. "On the Ontological Mystery," p. 39.
25. "Obedience and Fidelity," p. 133.
26. Creative Fidelity, Ch. VIII, "Creative Fidelity," pp. 166-67;
"Obedience and Fidelity," p. 134; Homo Viator, "Sketch of a
Phenomenology and a Metaphysic of Hope," pp. 29-67, especially
pp. 60-61.
130
27. Creative Fidelity, Ch. IV, "Phenomenological Notes on Being in a
Situation," pp. 97-100; "On the Ontological Mystery," p. 40.
28. "Obedience and Fidelity," pp. 128-32
29. Ibid., pp. 129-32; Présence Gabriel Marcel, Cahier 4, Paris, Aubier,
1983, “Gabriel Marcel et les injustices de ce temps. La
responsabilité de philosophe”, "Testament philosophique,"
(Vienna, September 1968), pp. 130, 132-33.
30. "Obedience and Fidelity," pp. 127-28.
31. "On the Ontological Mystery," pp. 37-38.
131
Chapter VII. Colombyre or the Torch of Peace: The Role of PersonCommunities
in Living Creative Fidelity to Values.
Creative fidelity is one of the central and most significant themes in
the thought of Gabriel Marcel. The present chapter examines one
aspect of this exceedingly rich theme, focusing upon Marcel'
s inquiry into
the possibility of living with creative fidelity to humanizing values in the
face of a situation threatening their survival.
To retrace Marcel'
s reflective clarification of this topic this chapter
will examine the development of his thought through his dramatic and
philosophic works: Colombyre or the Torch of Peace, a comedy in
three acts written in 1937, and "The Dangerous Situation of Ethical
Values," an essay of philosophic reflection written in 1943.(1) This
fresh approach to studying Gabriel Marcel's work is intended both to
illustrate the important interconnections between his dramatic and
philosophic works and to permit a faithful portrayal of the clarification he
brings to the question of the possibility of creative fidelity to values in a
dangerous situation wherein their survival is menaced.
The procedure of the study will be as follows. First, the distinctive
features of Marcel'
s drama will be summarized with a view toward
identifying its relation to his philosophic reflection. Second, the play
Colombyre will be examined in order to sketch the situation it conveys and
to summarize the questions it raises. Third, the essay "The Dangerous
Situation of Ethical Values" will be seen to illustrate the clarification
philosophic reflection brings to questions underlying an existential
situation. Fourth, the findings on the significance of dramatic approaches
to philosophic reflections will be summarized as well as the
clarification they bring to our understanding of the indispensable role of
person communities in providing for the survival of values.
Existential theater, as Marcel conceives it, communicates a
concrete situation that enables the author and the audience to
consciously participate in it. The development of the dramatic action
evokes an awareness of the fundamental antinomies characterizing the
human condition. The drama evolves among persons whose attitudes
and alternate stances of interpretation the audience can recognize as
being on some level their own. The distinctive dramatic element in
existential theater is the emergence and heightening of consciousness
132
for both the drama'
s characters and the audience. The successful final
act of an existential drama is not one that settles all the problematic
elements of the situation, but one that brings a certain dawning of light.(2)
Marcel's theater focuses on the dramatic issue of whether, in a
given concrete situation, a certain quality of life or more precisely a
certain quality of interpersonal communion is possible. At the end of his
plays, author, protagonists, and audience alike arrive at a certain
consciousness of this existential issue, the awareness of which enables
them to be beneficiaries of a certain diffuse light in which to carry on the pursuit of
their existential inquiry. The complementary role of philosophic reflection is to
bring this awareness of existential questions and light to another, higher level of
consciousness and clarification.(3)
Marcel's philosophic essays interpret the existential situation and
articulate its existential questions in more general and fundamental
terms. The critical analysis and dialectical reasoning of philosophic reflection
shed light on the fundamental antinomies of the human condition by
identifying their root sources. At the same time, phenomenological analysis
clarifies the requisite attitudes and conditions of possibility for gathering
ontological resources that would enable one to transcend these
antinomies and authentically realize one's noblest and deepest
possibilities.
Philosophic reflection continues the questioning to which
existential drama gives rise and through a more rigorous style of inquiry
brings it to a level of critically reasoned clarification. Yet, philosophic reflection
continually draws on the personal engagement in the quest and the concrete
approaches to reflection which existential theater can provide.
Let us now consider Marcel'
s dramatic approach to a situation
wherein the survival of values is dangerously imperiled. Colombyre or the
Torch of Peace is set in a Swiss mountain resort in the summer of 1937,
that ominous period before the outbreak of World War II. The play
represents in farcical fashion a caricature of a peace colony, tracing the
complacent vanity of its members, the vagaries of its spirit and goals, and the
fragmenting dissolution that becomes its fate. Its style is marked by clever wit,
deftly drawn caricatures, sharp-edged humor, ever-present irony, and a
comic sense of the ridiculous. The play satirizes the flaws and foibles that
undermine the "Colombyre" project'
s goal of being "A Torch of Peace." Yet,
ironically, its final scene of dissolution touches a chord of nostalgia for the
possibility of what might have been, or what perhaps someday might be.
133
The first act introduces a strange collection of characters who have bought
shares in a Swiss mountain villa called "Colombyre." While this
international group seems in some vague way to have as its ambition
the preservation and promotion of peace, it quickly becomes apparent
that there are sorely lacking any bonds of fraternal love, any kind of
consensus about the nature of this collectivity, and any common
commitment toward the realization of its goals.
The second act reveals the vanity of "Colombyre’s” pretentions.
The various plans for radiating peace fail, while the animosity and open
hostility among its members increase. "Colombyre," instead of being a
hearth of peace, becomes a hot-bed of strife.
Act three traces the final fragmentation of the "Colombyre"
experiment. Its dissolution develops apace with the unraveling of the
mystery of the old Russian’s violent death. Speculations,
accusations, recriminations, plots of assassination, and startling
betrayals abound. As the specter of violent death approaches, the
option of flight rather than fight wins popular consent. A note scribbled
before the cook'
s hasty departure warns of immanent disaster, and the
deciphering of its message spreads panic for fear of a time bomb. All
flee in disarray, deserting "Colombyre." Silent in the aura of sunset,
"Colombyre" appears to two young lovers as an idyllic setting for a
haven of peace. They leave. Explosion. Curtain.
The experiment at "Colombyre" failed. Its pretentions of being a
refuge and a radiating center for peace were farcical and doomed.
Instead of promoting peace and life, the experiment fomented
dissension, destruction, and death. The end of Colombyre certainly
raises the issue as to whether all such efforts to ensure the survival of
peace are equally ridiculous. Yet, the irony of the final scene, wherein
the young couple envisions this site as one day being a radiating center
for international peace, does raise the question of whether a personcommunity
could ever contribute effectively to the survival and radiance
of peace.
At face value Colombyre seems to ridicule the possibility of a
person-community actually resourcing and effectively radiating
peace in this world. However, Colombyre is no mere farcical
comedy, it is also a satire. Thus, as Colombyre sketches the tragic
comic flaws of a ridiculous caricature of a peace center, it also
134
brings into relief and focus paths of inquiry about what the essential
features and distinctive traits of a genuine community of creative
fidelity might be.
Questions are raised about the possibility and nature of an
international community with a bond of fraternal love, a Personcommunity
animated by a spirit and light from above, and about the
requisite conditions and attitudes for resourcing fidelity to values and
extending their realization in this world.
In a subsequent essay, “The Dangerous Situation of Ethical
Values," written in December 1943, Marcel articulates his philoscphic
reflections on the possibility of living creative fidelity to humanizing
values in a situation wherein their survival is seriously threatened.
The preliminary sketch in this reflection stresses that personcommunity
is the indispensable context for genuine creative fidelity to
values. Values are real and not merely ideas when they are incarnate,
that is, realized and embodied within the lives of individual human
persons. One's response to values is incarnately expressed toward the
concrete reality of individual human persons with, and for whom, values
are to be realized. Consistently, one's ethical response is a personal
commitment to promote the realization and embodiment of humanizing
values and is addressed to that cause as a suprapersonal reality.
Thus, one'
s commitment to promote value with and for other
persons engages one in a particular type of unity, which holds
together a number of persons within a life they share. In a spirit of
loyalty, one'
s engagement in the cause of a suprapersonal reality,
promoting the realization and embodiment of life'
s values with and
for persons, leads to the inclusion of all members of the human
community as those with and for whom one strives to see values
realized and embodied.(4)
Marcel shows that it is man himself in the unity of his life who is in
danger of death. This peril, he notes, applies equally to the concrete
individual person as a whole, and to the human race considered as a
flowing out or expansion of an essence. Man is threatened and in
danger of death by severance from the ontological foundation of life,
and also by the separation that alienates him from humankind.(5)
Many forces contribute to the perilous situation. For over four
hundred years atheism in our civilization has continually undermined
135
the natural foundations of life upon which faith and virtue grew. For the
last century and a half, naturalist and reductionist philosophies have
desacralized and profaned life. A general spirit of abstraction has
removed the reality of life and concrete approaches to its values from
the sphere of philosophic study. Techniques of control, leveling, and
debasement have aided man in diminishing his humanity. Thus, man
has lost both contact with the dignity and depth of his life and faith in
himself and humankind.(6)
Marcel warns that any attempt to save values must be clearly
envisioned and lived with constant vigilance, lest by oversimplification or
facile schematization, it should tend to aggravate the fissure that is
developing at the center of the human mass. Marcel then proceeds to
envisage various alternative stances that propose to promote values.
He indicates the difficulties and dangers that accompany each alternate
stance, and evaluates their appropriateness in function of their ability to
enhance those dimensions of unity, depth, and dignity in human life
that are in need of restoration and renewal. By successively
analyzing alternative positions and identifying both the
presuppositions that underlie and the consequences that flow from
them, Marcel evolves a critical identification of the requisite
conditions of possibility for the survival of values. The descriptive
clarification that accompanies his critical investigation also develops
a phenomenological sketch of appropriate ways to provide for the
survival and regeneration of values.
To the proposal that would count solely on social, economic,
and political techniques to effectuate humanization, Marcel warns
that such strictly tellurian mystiques do not draw on resources
capable of regenerating the moral quality of life. He also warns that
the operationalization of such tellurian mystiques carries the danger
of aggravating the fragmentation of humanity into opposing groups
of domination and subjugation and establishing relations of envy and
resentment in the struggle for possession of the world.(7)
In view of the dangers and risk of compromising the moral quality
of life involved in such collaboration, there is a temptation to withdraw
from such efforts. Yet, to abandon the effort to promote values entails a
betrayal of life and the very notion of hope for its salvation.(8)
Pursuing another direction, Marcel inquires as to what the stance
should be of those who believe in values in a situation that includes
136
others who are either non-believers, indifferent, or desire to merely
survive a bad situation with the least possible harm.
Should the believer patronize and attempt to bestow values on
less fortunate individuals? Should the believer preach particular truths
to others who are still in the darkness of ignorance or error? No
attitudes could be more likely to incite envy and spite and thus deepen
the rift of misunderstanding and resentment. Furthermore, these
stances falsify the reality of the situation. The believer cannot claim to
give something he has, for the reality of light and grace is not something
one has.
To act as if it were is to denature and distort its reality. Faith or
grace is genuine on the condition that it inhabits a person, not only as
radiance, but also as humility. Even this attitude may seem hypocritical
to the unbeliever. The believer must practice constant vigilance lest he
merely make a gesture of what he imagines humility to be.(9)
Marcel suggests that there is a Christian maieutic more
appropriate to healing rifts and more fruitful for communicating an
experience of values. A regard of love can awaken the other's
consciousness of his divine filiation. One does not bring or give the
other anything, rather one addresses one's act of adoration to God's
Présence within the other’s life. This is more difficult to the extent that a
person remains closed in his self-complacent vanity.(10) Yet, to
communicate thus serves not only to strengthen the suprapersonal
community that binds one with this other, but also to strengthen the
bonds that make universal community possible,(11)
Marcel observes that upon further reflection even the division
between believer and unbeliever is belied when one recognizes those
vast regions within ones own life wherein the gospel has not yet been
preached, Such resistant dimensions of one's self and action are often
the most, and sometimes the only, part of life that is visible to
others.(12)
A proper approach toward providing for the survival of values now
begins to emerge. It is creative of that unity in life which is indispensable
for resourcing a renewal of values. Individuals who are concerned for
the survival of values can together, and in the context of a personcommunity,
explore and rediscover the natural foundations of human
life and values. Such an exploration of the peri-Christian or natural
137
foundations of life's values is capital. The survival and renewal of values
depends upon the restoration of that vital contact. Seeking humbly
together to rediscover the natural foundations of human life opens a
viable way to experience anew the present grace and revelation of
values carried by human life.
Within the life of a person-community that exercises the Christian
maieutic of love, the vital contact with the unity and depth of human life
can be restored. Through that the renewal and communication of
human and ethical values can occur. Individuals living a communion of
fraternal love and exercising a Christian maieutic can come to share
what is essential in each ones experience and heritage. Together they
can deepen the discovery and enrich the communication of the values
they come to share. Living this spirit of truth in the openness and depth
of their quest, the individual members can achieve a unity with a suprapersonal
reality of light and love that will make possible the gathering
and communication of those values they seek to embody with and for
one another and all humankind.
Marcel envisages the development of many small groups,
relearning how to live in conditions that are real, and in a light that at
their summit illumines the group they form with each other and the
things supporting them. He envisages this as the proper and
indispensable way in which the lacerated tissue of human life can be
regenerated. The guarantee of success for such undertakings is bound
up with the humility in which they originate and which shapes their first
objectives.(13)
Person-communities can effectuate and philosophers help to
formulate this regeneration of the lacerated tissue of human life and the
renewal and communication of values. Without this, man will be
condemned to an infra-animal existence of which our generation has
the painful privilege of witnessing the first apocalyptic symptoms.(14)
Marcel'
s essay identifies precisely the forces that menace, the
nature of what is at stake, and the stances that threaten to aggravate
rather than ameliorate the imperiled situation of human values. Hence,
Colombyre can be viewed as a dramatic representation of humankind'
s
plight. It traces the inadequacies in the attitudes of its membership as
the reason for the alienation and destruction which become the fate of
life at "Colombyre."
138
Marcel'
s essay identifies person-community as the appropriate and
indispensable manner of effectuating the survival and regeneration of
values in human life. More important, the essay identifies the essential
traits of life and spirit which enable a person-community to realize a
genuine creative fidelity to values. In this, success depends upon
humble and heroic realization of man'
s noblest possibilities, which only
the dialogue of freedom and grace can assure. This clarification of the
spirit and life which animates a genuine person-community'
s realization
of creative fidelity to values stands in stark contrast to the tragic comic
caricature satirized in Colombyre.
Dramatic imagination and critical conceptual clarification are
mutually illuminating. They further the ongoing human effort to achieve
concrete awareness of the existential situation and bring questions to
that level of conscious elucidation that should characterize human
understanding and enlighten ethical response.
139
Notes to Chapter VII.. Colombyre or the Torch of Peace: The Role of
Person-Community in Living Creative Fidelity to Values
1. Gabriel Marcel, Colombyre ou le brasier de la paix, in Théâtre
Comique, Paris, Edition Albin Michel, 1947, pp. 7-154. Colombyre
or The Torch of Peace, English version by Joseph Cunneen, Two
Plays by Gabriel Marcel: The Lantern and The Torch of Peace,
University Press of America, Lanham, MD, forthcoming. Gabriel
Marcel, "The Dangerous Situation of Ethical Values" in Homo Viator,
an Introduction to a Metaphysic of Hope, trans. by Emma Craufurd,
New York: Harper Torchbook, 1962, pp. 155-65.
2. Gabriel Marcel, Le Seuil Invisible, Paris, Edition Grasset, 1914,
Préface, pp. 1-8.
3. Gabriel Marcel, "De la recherche philosophique" in
Entretiens autour de Gabriel Marcel, Neuchâtel, à la
Baconnière, 1976, pp. 9-19.
4. Gabriel Marcel, "The Dangerous Situation of Ethical Values," pp.
155-56.
5. Ibid., p, 156.
6. Ibid., pp. 156, 161, 164 passim.
7. Ibid., pp. 157-58.
8. Ibid., p. 159.
9. Ibid., pp. 159-61.
10. Ibid., p. 160.
11. Ibid., p. 156.
12. Ibid., p. 160.
13. Ibid., p. 164.
14. Ibid., p. 165.
140
Chapter VIII. The Sting: Threatening the Foundations of Fidelity
Through the William James lectures that he delivered at Harvard
University in 1961, Gabriel Marcel amply illustrated that he considered
his theater a privileged way of access to his philosophic inquiries.
Marcel developed this idea repeatedly, not only in his Harvard
lectures, The Existential Background of Human Dignity, but also in
works of drama criticism and in his two major essays of
autobiographical reflection.(1)
The works we shall focus on in this chapter are The Sting, a play
written in 1936 and staged in 1937, originally entitled Le Dard, and Man
Against Mass Society, a collection of philosophic essays first published
in French under the title Les hommes contre l'
humain in 1951 and then
published in English in Great Britain in 1952 and in the United States
in 1962. These works proceed in distinctively different though quite
complementary fashions to identify the forces of degradation that
undermine human dignity and threaten the survival of individual persons
by demeaning spiritual values.(2)
While Marcel'
s earlier works usually focused on questions that
affect the emptiness or fullness, inauthenticity or authenticity of
individuals' lives, The Sting is perhaps prophetic in that it focuses on the
mood and temper of a society wherein the survival of spiritual values is
seriously threatened. Yet, whatever topic an investigation researches,
Marcel'
s approach is always the same. He inquires as to how the lives
of individual persons will be concretely affected by the particular issue at
hand.
Marcel felt that drama let audiences enter into the life world
depicted on stage and even into the inner consciousness of certain
characters who communicated their growing awareness of the tragic
dimension within their lives. Since the dramas often highlight questions
and open perspectives of light, especially in their denouements,
audiences have access to the life situation of others and can thus enter
into a shared experience of the mystery occurring on stage. The dramas
present questions as these challenge individual lives. Theaters role is
not to demonstrate or explain, but rather to present life. Marcel'
s theater
141
invites reflection on certain issues that philosophy can subsequently
investigate critically and then interpret through rational analysis.
In this study we shall look first at the play, The Sting, considering
an analysis Marcel gave to it in the Préface to (The Secret is in the
Isles).(3) Then we shall examine Marcel'
s subsequent philosophic
consideration of some of the issues the play brings to light. These
philosophic issues we take from the several essays included in the book
Man Against Mass Society. (4)
Gabriel Marcel'
s Analysis of The Sting,
excerpted from (“The Secret is in the Isles”).
"The Sting”, written in 1936 and staged in 1937, reflects the
disorientation of mind and spirit affecting people before the outbreak of
World War II. I must say also that in the case of this drama as in most
all of my plays, the creative inspiration came in terms of two exceptional
individuals who in their reciprocal relationships imposed themselves on
my imagination. Around these main protagonists other people of
secondary importance grouped themselves. These are presented in a
somewhat satirical fashion. One might say there was a center and an
epicenter. Surely the center is Eustache Soreau, an intellectual who
came from more than modest circumstances. Though he has attained a
certain social status, he, cannot allow himself to accept his success,
which he views as somehow involving a betrayal.
"The epicenter is Werner Schnee, a German artist, who has
become a refugee in France, not so much out of necessity as out of
solidarity with a Jewish friend who was persecuted and who will
probably not live long after the terrible treatment he received.
"These two, Eustache and Werner, knew each other in Germany
when Eustache was a teaching assistant at Marburg University. They
became friends, but what will become of that friendship? Will it
withstand the stresses of a cohabitation during which each of them will
experience, as it were, the other as a sort of judgment or condemnation
of what he lives or aspires to be?
142
"Eustache and Werner are not the only protagonists in the play.
First of all, there is Beatrice, Eustache'
s wife. And there is her father, M.
Durand-Fresnel, a narrow-minded politician, a conservative socialist,
who would just fit as a chairperson of a masquerade committee.
"There is no question that Eustache has loved Beatrice for herself
and not because of but rather despite the advantages that accrued from
their marriage. But his love has been, one might say, poisoned by the
idea that their marriage has been advantageous for him, and by that
very fact liable to be considered as a sort of desertion. Should Beatrice
have refused to accept the dowry that her parents gave her? Should
she now, in order to please Eustache, break off relations with her family
under the pretext that they are secure bourgeois? She has too much
good sense for that, and her family means too much to her (even
though she recognizes their mediocrity) for her to yield to a demand that
she finds excessive and quite unreasonable. She has mixed emotions
about this. She admires, to a certain extent, Eustache’
s detachment and
disinterestedness, but on a deeper level she considers suspect what is
impure in Eustache’s protestations. And it is here that Gertrude
Heuzard, a grammar school teacher, an extremist of the radical left,
comes into the picture. She and Eustache were close comrades before
Eustache'
s marriage. She has just recently been suspended from her
job on the allegation that she has disseminated antipatriotic propaganda
among her students. In that respect she can be considered a victim,
and Eustache envies her more than he pities her. She has the merit of
having made her actions conform to her ideas. Eustache feels judged by
her as a deserter. She is a personification of his bad conscience. But
Beatrice, who is intelligent and sensitive, perceives what is essentially
equivocal about this woman. Beatrice suspects that basically Gertrude
is in love with Eustache and considers Beatrice as a rival. She tells her
husband this feeling of hers, but he simply refuses to acknowledge it.
Eustache has only disdain for the realm of affectivity; in this, as in other
matters, he reasons only as a function of his ideology. To Beatrice this
would be mere childishness that would make her smile, if it were not for
the fact that the rift between her husband and herself was growing. The
arrival of Werner Schnee and his wife Gisela only serves to widen the
gap.
143
"Werner is essentially an artist--not a composer, but a singer, a
gifted and impassioned interpreter of the songs of classical musicians.
He was never active politically. As a matter of fact, he is not interested
in politics and probably even disdains it. He left Germany, as I have
said, in sympathy with the persecuted Jewish pianist who was his
accompanist. What matters for him are individual persons and
relationships between people. He distrusts the abstractions with which
fanatics nourish themselves. In such circumstances, how could a
conflict not inevitably erupt between him and Eustache, who is precisely a
man of abstractions, a man of "isms"? Eustache reproaches him for
not establishing contact with other political refugees, for not joining one
of the organized groups that already exists. For Eustache there is a
category of refugee that implies certain obligations that one must meet.
But, in Werner'
s eyes, that category as such is nonexistent. There is no
reason to affiliate himself with people whom he doesn'
t know and who
probably would be uncongenial if he did know them. But Eustache
judges such individualism as reactionary and consequently scandalous.
Is it only an ideological difference that sets these two men off in
opposition to one another? Eustache, without admitting it, is annoyed
by the admiration that Beatrice obviously manifests for Werner. Can
one speak of jealousy in the strict sense of the term? Perhaps not. But
Eustache has a vague presentiment of usurpation, which offends him.
Moreover, he will discover with profound irritation that Beatrice and
Werner talked about him in his absence, doubtless to discuss his situation
and maybe even to criticize him. He cannot bear being treated as a third
party by those two, and there is here a particularly meaningful
illustration of one of the fundamental themes of my philosophic
reflections.
"It seems unnecessary to me to literally tell the story of the whole
play. I merely wanted to clarify the essential elements of its dramatic
structure. This play is, in my opinion, one of the most characteristic of all
the plays I have written. It’s not merely a psychological drama; rather it
portrays, as I have said, a definite and important moment in our
history. But even more important, it is hard for me not to find a
prophetic dimension to this play. Here I am thinking, of course, of the
concluding lines of the final scene.
"Werner has decided to return to Germany, certainly not to accept
the comfortable position that an impresario offered to him, which
would have presupposed his surrender to an execrable regime. He has
144
discovered that there is something within himself and his songs that is
his way of participating in life creatively, something that touches
people and by which he can help them to live. As he is essentially a
noble person, he is repulsed by the idea that these gifts could become
merely a means for social success. He asks himself--and the author
asks with him, without in any way answering the question--if he has not
to some extent become infected by the contagious sickness that
plagues Eustache. But there is more; he discovers that he loves
Beatrice and that probably his love is reciprocated. But how can he live
with the idea of betraying Eustache, who, after all, has been his friend?
On this basis he feels the obligation to leave, to tear himself away from a
temptation which, in the long run, he is not sure that he could resist. The
moment of decision is all the more critical since Eustache has become
Gertrude’
s lover, and Beatrice is at the end of her strength and just
about ready to leave him. Still there would be something base and
despicable in taking advantage of this set of circumstances.
"Werner: You cannot abandon him. You must always remember
that you are the wife of a pauper...Poverty is not a lack of money, nor is
it lack of success. Eustache has had money, he'
s had success; yet he
remains poor and keeps getting poorer. Probably he will never recover
from his kind of poverty. It is the great evil of our times, and its
spreading like the plague. They haven'
t yet found a physician who can
heal it. They don'
t even know how to recognize the illness. There's a
chance artists may escape, even if they do go hungry. And also the
faithful who by their prayer.... All other people are in danger.
"Beatrice: You are asking me to live with a leper...
'Werner: The leprosariums are going to proliferate on this earth, I
fear. It will be a grace reserved for very few to live there, knowing
that they are living with lepers and yet not hold them in horror.
Even more than a grace. How do you say? Via-te-cum, a viaticum.
"Beatrice: I am not brave enough, Werner, I assure you.
"Werner: You will think of me, as I think of Rudolf. Later on I shall
be in you a living presence, as Rudolf still is in me. You will
remember then what I told you here a few weeks ago. If there
were only the living, Beatrice...
145
The words he spoke were these: "
If there were only the living, I
think life on this earth would be quite impossible.”
"Those who have read Man Against Mass Society will have no
difficulty in recognizing that this prophetic word not only announced the
ideas that were developed in the essays that I collected under that
title, but also pictured in advance the terrible situations that developed
in France and other countries after the Second World War. But what I
want to underline here, appropriate to this introduction, is that the
subsequent reflections developed in connection with an individual
person, namely Eustache, who came to me with his particularity, and
also from imagining someone who was oriented in the opposite direction
and what one might think of the other. Nothing is less like an
argument, or a demonstration of a thesis. It is a question rather of
showing and awakening, by means that are not unlike those the
musician uses to awaken consciences concretely to a terrible
disorder, yet beyond that an order that transcends conceptualization,
but which each one of us can attain by means of recollection and
prayer".(5)
Marcel considers The Sting as one of his most significant dramas.
It deals, he writes in "The Drama of the Soul in Exile," with the suffering
of our contemporary world.(6) What is this suffering? It is a kind of
spiritual poverty, a sickness that threatens the survival of humanity on
earth. When Marcel discussed The Sting as he did in The Existential
Background of Human Dignity in Chapter VII on "Human Dignity," and
in a Préface to the re-edition of (The Sting) along with (The Emissary)
and (The End of Time) in the book (The Secret is in the Isles), he
quoted the final dialogue between Beatrice and Werner from the final
scene of The Sting .17) These final exchanges let us hear in the words
of people who are living the dramatic challenge their concrete
perception of the tragic sickness affecting the masses today and the
heroic action required of those who must live in that situation but who
hope to do so without succumbing to its poisonous sting.
Our procedure in the second part of this chapter will be similar.
Recognizing that Marcel'
s theater is a privileged way of access to his
philosophic thought, we shall reconstruct scenes from the play and
perspectives from the philosophic analyses collected in Man Against
Mass Society, as together these clarify questions about what the Sting
146
is, and how people can be preserved from its infection.
Early in the book Man Against Mass Society Marcel observed that
between Frederich Nietzsche’s declaration that "God is dead" and the
current phenomenon that "man is in his death throes," there is no
logical connection, but there is a connection that is concrete and
existential.(8) A spiritual poverty such as is presented in The Sting and
commented upon in Man Against Mass Society is only possible where
belief in God and transcendent values is absent.(9) Yet Marcel also
stated that "it is perhaps by starting from the statement '
man is in his
death throes'
that we may be able to question once more the statement, '
God is dead’, and to discover that God is living after all."(10)
In that same essay, "What is a free man?", Marcel clarifies that:
"To say that man is in his death throes is only to say that man today finds
himself facing, not some external event,...but rather possibilities of
complete self-destruction inherent in himself...(possibilities) of a
spiritual destruction wrought by techniques of human degradation."(11)
With these preliminary perspectives noted, let us take up our
analysis of the play and Marcel's philosophic commentaries about the
sickness plaguing our civilization.
In the first two scenes of Act One, Eustache Soreau shows his
dis-ease about his poor social origin, evidenced by his irritation over the
contrast between his mother'
s obvious lack of cultural refinement and the
mannerly affectations of his wife'
s family. Yet it is Eustache'
s contact
with Gertrude Heuzard that precipitates his showing symptoms of that
particular form of bad conscience that Marcel saw as a malady of our
times. The bad conscience that Eustache displays is, Marcel noted, very
like the phenomenon of resentment as Max Scheler and Frederich
Nietzsche have described it.(12)
It is Eustache'
s interaction with Gertrude that discloses the
dynamics of bad conscience. Eustache felt uncomfortable about his
humble origins, but he also felt guilty about having risen above them.
Yet it is Gertrude who, judging him in terms of a militant's ideology
convicts him of guilt. Eustache, by a strange complicity, interiorized
Gertrude'
s judgment, and in a spirit of condemnation convicts himself of
147
betraying the people by having deserted their condition for the sake of
bourgeois privileges.
The degradation of others, and the overthrow of values through
the phenomenon of resentment works as follows. The "oppressed"
convict the "elite" of guilt, degrade and disgrace them, and remove them
from positions of privilege and power. By this process of
condemnation, the oppressed become the powerful, and the elite
become powerless.
Indeed Beatrice perceived rightly that Gertrude not only disdained
Eustache in the light of her militant ideology, but that she also wanted
to gain power over him and possess him and thus considered Beatrice
her rival.(13)
Marcel observed that in many radical socialist and peoples
democratic parties, although the phenomenon is not limited to these
groups, the ideal of equality is one that envisages reducing everyone
to the lowest common denominator. Such an ideal of equality, he
notes, is not congruent with either liberty or fraternity. This claiming of
equality strives to eliminate spiritual values by degradation and to
suppress any admiration of excellence. The struggle for equality is
often founded on a spirit of envy and meanness, not on a reverence or
admiration for the human dignity of persons as created by God, imago
Dei. (14)
Scene 4 of Act I, the scene wherein Eustache engages his inlaws
in conversation, further demonstrates how the attitude and
atmosphere of spiritual degradation spreads. Eustache now becomes
the agent inducing bad conscience, a technique of which he was so
recently a victim. This scene also shows ideas that Marcel explores
quite thoroughly in Man Against Mass Society. We see that the
spreading of an ideology does not proceed by carefully reasoned
analyses of concrete situations, nor is it communicated through civil
rational discourse. Conversations are more like diatribes of partisan
politics. The techniques used are those of propaganda. A militant claims
to possess the truth, and he or she is willing to coerce others until they
adhere to that conviction. Conversations exchange slogans of
propaganda that resemble battle cries more than ideas. Marcel also
notes that most often these slogans are adhered to more by passion
148
than by intelligent understanding. Propagandizing manipulates ideas for
the sake of power and does not operate in a spirit of truth. It also
attempts to manipulate opponents, to find their weak points and exploit
them, to confound their arguments and make them appear foolish and
in error.(15)
From the time of Eustache’s conversation with the DurandFresnels,
Act I, scene 4, and then the arrival of Werner Schnee and his
wife Gisela, the difference between Eustache and Werner becomes
clear, as does the tension of opposition that will develop in this
cohabitation, even though these two men were once friends at Marburg
University. Through this contrast and the interaction of Eustache as
point and Werner as counterpoint it becomes evident what on the one
hand contributes to the process of spiritual degradation and what on the
other hand serves as a basis of resistance to such dehumanization.
Eustache is an intellectual animated by a spirit of abstraction, caring only
for political goals and ideals. Werner is a dedicated artist, who cares
for music and individual persons. A spirit of abstraction and a disdain for
life are part of the process of spiritual degradation. Care for individual
persons and a faithful commitment to creatively communicate the
transcendent values of life to others are the lifelines of a strength that
can resist such dehumanization.
Act II begins with Werner singing a Goethe song, Gisela
accompanying him at the piano. In the conversation that ensues,
Eustache affirms that he does not like music, finding it valuable only if it
promotes the spirit or goals of the party. Eustache goads Werner to
join a political alliance or a refugee action group. Werner avows that
he finds politics distasteful. What he cares about now is music and
Rudolf Schontal, his accompanist--a real person, who has suffered
terribly from political persecution and probably will die as a result. Gisela
offers that she does not want to battle with a dead man, she wants to
go home to Germany where she had a life, her house, her family, her
friends. Werner muses, "Oh Gisela, if there were only the living, I think
this world would be quite uninhabitable."(16)
In a lecture entitled "The Paradox of a Philosopher-Dramatist"
(17) Marcel affirmed that a spirit of abstraction is at the root of all
fanaticism and fratricide. He develops that idea in the Man Against
Mass Society’s essay "The Spirit of Abstraction as a Factor Making for
149
War."(1)
A spirit of abstraction is necessary in order to regard another
human being as “the enemy.” Through a spirit of abstraction one can kill
a "Nazi," a "commie," or a "whatever" not envisioned as an individual
human person. A spirit of abstraction is, moreover, a factor for waging
war in that often one kills or maims for the sake of an abstraction, "the
People," "Justice," "the Party," or even "Peace." A spirit of abstraction is
an essential part of the process of propagandizing and the
development of a fanaticized consciousness. A spirit of abstraction is
radically opposed to a concrete approach that considers every issue as
it affects the lives of individual persons, whom one continues to regard
as individuals created by God, even imago Dei whose being includes a
particle of the divine reality. This latter perspective allows one to
perceive that sacred dimension of persons that reveals a true
universality concretely present in persons, one disregarded by a
spirit of abstraction that falsely fires up fanaticism and incites the
masses.(19)
The path that Eustache and Gertrude'
s relationship follows
indicates the role of disdain for life in techniques of degradation.
Gertrude comes to Eustache'
s home to tell him that she is going to
commit suicide. Her life has led her to a point where she expects
nothing more from it, and so she plans to end it. Eustache, though
aware that there may be some sort of blackmail involved, goes to be
with Gertrude. In taking this decisive action, he insults, soils, and
repudiates everything he had previously held as valuable. He refuses a
promotion, insults his "friends" in the ministry of education, profanes his
house and marriage, bringing Gertrude to be there with him in his wife'
s
absence and telling his fatherin-law
that this is just the beginning of
militant action yet to come. In "Techniques of Degradation," Marcel cites
reports from World War II concentration camps which indicated that
techniques of degradation were intended to shame the victim so that he
or she appeared worthless in his or her own eyes, felt wholly at the
mercy of another, ceased to be an opponent worth reckoning with, and
provided to the executioner a feeling of delight and exaltation
comparable to the delight and exaltation of sacrilege.(20)
In the third act of The Sting, it appears as if all is lost. Everyone
associated with Eustache'
s household is to some extent afflicted by the
150
sting. Eustache has gone over to be with Gertrude and live out her
militant ways. M. Durand-Fresnel is offended by insult and ingratitude.
Eustache'
s mother and brother feel rejected and deeply hurt. Beatrice,
upon her return, finds that Eustache is effectively planning to leave her
and everything of their life together, to go and be with Gertrude. And
then Werner comes to announce his imminent departure for
Germany.
When Werner tells Beatrice of his plans to return to Germany, she
protests that it'
s suicide and pleads, asking how he can leave her alone
in this most terrible moment. And Werner explains his mind to her. It is
not a question of suicide; he plans to be with the oppressed and, by
sharing his gift of song, serve to quicken their sense of their human
dignity. Both Beatrice and Werner are intelligent and loving people who
care for individuals thoughtfully. Werner recognizes that he must go his
way, faithful to his commitment and Beatrice must continue in hers
though the persecution and suffering may be excruciating for them
both.
Werner acknowledges that indeed he and Beatrice do love each
other. Their love does not exempt them from the temptation to give
carnality full reign, yet in this case, their fidelity to higher values will
protect them. Thus Werner encourages Beatrice to stay with
Eustache, to be faithful to him and care for him even though the
situation may be horribly painful.
Werner adds that it is a grace given to very few to live among
those infected by the sting of spiritual poverty and degradation and
not hold them in disgust. Marcel wrote in Man Against Mass
Society, "Individual goodness is inconceivable without grace."(21)
He adds that it is an extraordinary grace that enables a person to
break the hellish cycle of reprisals and counter-reprisals that spiritual
degradation sets in motion.(22) Werner'
s decision to affirm human
dignity in concentration camps and his encouragement to Beatrice to
do likewise in her household is just such a decision to transcend the
force of spiritual degradation.
Werner'
s life as an artist witnesses how creative fidelity to
higher values is possible. Marcel observed that Werner, as an artist
consecrated to music, has his life totally given over to creatively
151
communicating this value with and for others. By thus living creative
fidelity to that spiritual value he is protected from the sting of spiritual
degradation.(23) Furthermore, his willingness to give his life, even to
the point of martyrdom, so that a spiritual value will be present among
others shows how one persons life, even after his death, can
resource creative fidelity in other people'
s lives. Werner witnesses
that communion with his friend Rudolf helped him to make his decision.
This communion he knows will also sustain him in his suffering and
death. On the strength of this witness he assures Beatrice that not
only an artist but also a true believer who can pray will be spared
from destruction by the spiritual sickness that menaces our time.
Werner'
s life and words assure Beatrice that she will not be alone.
She will find, through tender remembrance and prayer, a communion of
love and an assurance that he is with her, as Rudolf was with him. He
even assures her that, later on after his death, he will be for her like
a via te cum, a viaticum sharing his life in a way that a loved one
from beyond death can be here with us, strengthening us in our
weakness in time of persecution and death.(24)
The Sting ends on a note of hope. Even in the face of the
tragic situation wrought by spiritual poverty and degradation, we
discover that it is indeed possible to resist the sting by drawing on
transcendent spiritual resources deep within ourselves that enable
even heroic forms of creative fidelity. Reflection assures that the
grace to live such heroic fidelity will not be lacking to those whose
creative lives--like those of artists and true believers who pray--will be
resourced by the continuing life of someone who has died before us yet
continues to live on.
The study of Gabriel Marcel'
s theater and philosophy in concert
has enabled us to see in an existential and concrete way that a concern
for human beings in their death throes can bring us to the center point
within ourselves where we can recognize that in fact "God is not dead
but living"...beyond death, yes, living with and for us.(25)
In the process of his reflection as philosopher-dramatist Gabriel
Marcel has revealed something of his notion of personhood. His notion
is one that transcends by far the idea of equality of individuals as allotted
by materialist psychologies, philosophies, or ideologies, and exceeds
by far the level to which cultural propaganda of 1937, 1950'
s, 1960'
s,
152
1980'
s, or 2000'
s would reduce people'
s self-images. Marcel has let us
share in his perspectives that allow us to perceive persons as imago
Dei, and even experience the sacred depth and possibility of
interpersonal communion that assure the true existential background of
human dignity.(26)
The fidelity of the living finds its basis in the enduring fidelity of martyrs.
By their self-sacrificing love, their self-gift for others, they continue to live
on in survivors nourishing and supporting the fidelity of the living despite
the epidemic proportions of spiritual poverty in this world.
153
Notes to Chapter VIII. The Sting: Threatening the Foundations of
Fidelity
1. "An Autobiographical Essay" (Spring 1969) in The Philosophy of
Gabriel Marcel (Library of Living Philosophers Vol. XVII) ed. Paul
A. Schilpp and Lewis E. Hahn, LaSalle, Illinois, Open Court, 1984,
pp. 1-68; "An Essay in Autobiography" in The Philosophy of
Existentialism, Secaucus, New Jersey, The Citadel Press, 1956,
pp. 104-28; Introduction to The Existential Drama of Gabriel
Marcel, ed. F. J. Lescoe, West Hartford, Conn., McAuley Institute,
St. Joseph College, 1974; "My Dramatic Works as Viewed by the
Philosopher" in Searchings, New York, Newman, 1967, pp. 93-
118; "The Drama of the Soul in Exile" (July 1950) in Three Plays
by Gabriel Marcel, London, Secker & Warburg, 1952; New York,
Hill & Wang, 1965; The Existential Background of Human Dignity,
Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1963.
2. (The Sting), A Play in Three Acts. Le Dard, Paris, Plon, 1936,
reedited in Le Secret est dans les Iles, Paris, Plon, 1967, pp. 25-
153. Les Homnes contre l’humain, Paris, La Colombe, 1951; Man
Against Mass Society, Great Britain, 1952; Chicago, H. Regnery,
Gateway, 1962.
(The Secret is in the Isles), including a Préface ("The Secret is in
the Isles") and three plays, (The Sting), (The Emissary), and (The
End of Time), Paris: Plon, 1967, has not yet been translated into
English. Even though (The Sting) has not yet been translated and
published in English, its title has been underlined in the text of this
chapter to enable readers to easily recognize by the conventional
sign that The Sting is the title of the play analyzed in this chapter.
This underlining is a departure from the system employed in Part
Three of this book, wherein titles in English are not underlined in
order to indicate that a work has not yet been translated and
published in English.
3. Le Secret est dans les Iles, Paris, Plon, 1967, pp. 14-19.
4. Man Against Mass Society, Chicago, H. Regnery, Gateway, 1962.
"The Universal Against the Masses," I, II, pp. 1-11, 257-73;”What
is a Free Man?" pp. 13-25; "Lost Liberties," pp. 26-36;
"Techniques of Degradation," pp. 37-75; "Technological Progress
and Sin," pp. 76-101; "The Philosopher and the Contemporary
154
World," pp. 103-32; "The Fanaticized Consciousness," pp. 133-
52; "The Spirit of Abstraction, as a Factor Making for War," pp.
153-62; "The Crisis of Value in the Contemporary World," pp. 163-
92.
5. Le Secret est dans les Iles, pp. 14-19, quotes from (The Sting), Act III,
Scene 8, pp. 152-53.
6. ”The Drama of the Soul in Exile," p. 32.
7. The Existential Background of Human Dignity, Ch. VII, p.
122.
8. Man Against Mass Society, "What is a Free Man?" pp. 14-
15.
9. Ibid., pp. 22-23; "Techniques of Degradation," p. 67.
10. Man Against Mass Society, "What is a Free Man?" p. 15.
11. Ibid., p. 14.
12. Max Scheler, Ressentiment, New York, Schocken Books, 1972.
13. (The Sting), Act I, Scene 3; cf. Act II, Scene 9; Act III, Scenes 2,
3, 6.
14. Man Against Mass Society, "Lost Liberties," pp. 27, 28, 29, 35-36;
"Techniques of Degradation," p. 67.
15. Man Against Mass Society, "Techniques of Degradation,"
pp. 37, 49-52, 69, 73, 75.
16. (The Sting), Act II, scene 10, p. 121.
17. Gabriel Marcel: Le Paradoxe de philosophe-dramaturge,
Realisations Sonores: Hughes De Salle, Collection Francais de
Notre Temps Nous Confie, Sous le patronage de lAlliance
Française, presentation écrite sur la pochette de Marc Blancpain,
no date.
18. Man Against Mass Society, "The Spirit of Abstraction, as a
155
Factor Making for War." pp. 153-62.
19. Man Against Mass Society, "The Spirit of Abstraction,..." pp. 156-
58, 160; "The Universal Against the Masses," pp. 4, 259, 262, 267,
273; "Techniques of Degradation," p. 67.
20. (The Sting), Act II, Scene 6; Act III, scene 6. Man Against Mass
Society, "Techniques of Degradation," pp. 42-45, 46, 47, 48;
"Technological Progress and Sin," pp. 79, 92-93.
21. Man Against Mass Society, "Lost Liberties," pp. 30, 93;
Jeanne Parain-Vial, "La Grace dans Le Dard," to appear.
22. Man Against Mass Society, "Techniques of Degradation," p.
48.
23. The Existential Background of Human Dignity, pp. 124-25; Man
Against Mass Society, "Technical Progress and Sin," p. 100;
"Degradation of the Idea of Service," p. 203.
24. "The Sting," pp. 152-53. The Existential Background of Human
Dignity , pp. 124-25.
25. Man Against Mass Society, "The Universal Against the Masses,"
pp. 15, 259, 266-67.
26. Man Against Mass Society, "What is a Free Man?" pp. 22-25; "Lost
Liberties,"
pp. 29, 35; "Techniques of Degradation," pp. 57, 67;
"Technical Progress and Sin," pp. 79, 92-93; "The Spirit of
Abstraction," p. 160; "
The Universal Against the Masses," pp. 4, 266-
67, 273.
156
Chapter IX. Rome Is No Longer In Rome: Challenge for Creative
Incarnations of Fidelity
Rome Is No Longer in Rome is a play that in its own time
created quite a stir both for its timeliness and the power of its
message. It was originally produced at the Hébertot Theater in
Paris, April 19, 1951.(1) Its composition was occasioned by the
atmosphere in France and other parts of Western Europe, where
people had lived through two major wars in close succession.
People felt the impending advent of a political or military coup that
would introduce a Soviet or at least a "popular front" regime. Still,
the situation depicted in the play has counterparts in our current
situations.
Significant questions are brought to light, questions that are
personal and that have relevance to the current plight of western
civilization. How can one be genuinely faithful to ones heritage of
spiritual values and communicate them or creatively incarnate them
in a world where these kinds of values are foreign? The foreign land
in question may be a territory or nation or it may mean a material
civilization where spiritual values are unknown, devalorized, or
forgotten.
After a brief summary of the play we shall reflect on a few
questions to clarify their significance with reference to the drama
and the philosophic writings of Marcel.
Rome Is No Longer in Rome depicts the Laumière family as
they live out their decision to emigrate to another land rather than
be destroyed by the events that menace their survival in France.
This play is certainly one of Marcel'
s finest works. Rather than
depict barricades and trenches, Marcel portrays in five acts the
psychological drama that some individuals undergo as they form a
decision and struggle to find its worth in the trying circumstances of
their lives.
The first three acts deal with the drama of making the decision
to leave France. The last two reveal the drama of giving meaning to
that move.
157
Renée Laumière, without consulting her husband, Pascal, has
made arrangements for him to be offered a teaching position at a newly
founded university in San Felipe. When Pascal learns that there is a
professorial appointment and a welcome for him and his family in San
Felipe, he is disconcerted. Certainly he wants his wife and children to
be safe, but he himself had not planned to leave France.
He is helped in his decision by his nephew Marc André, who
announces his plan to leave France with a friend whose father can get
them jobs in Africa. Marc André begs Pascal to take care of his mother,
Esther, so that she will not feel forsaken. While they exchange views on
various topics, Marc André wants to test his uncle's strength. Would
Pascal subscribe to the following commitment by one of his friends'
fathers, Professor Moreuil?
I don'
t know what that moment will make of me, perhaps a rag.
I
'
m not presuming on my own strength alone. I'
m counting on
God, that he will not abandon me, that he will save me from a
final disaster. Either he will take me to himself, or he will give
me the strength to withstand the torture. (Act II, Scene I)(2)
Pascal responds that in all honesty he cannot state that conviction
as his own. He sees that he has only the more abstract notion of his
sense of integrity and the hope of his loyalty to French "honor" and
"patriotism." Marc André then inquires whether the orphaned children
inherit this sense of "honor" by proxy.
After a sharp exchange between Pascal and his wife Renée, it
seems that there are no solid reasons left for remaining in France.
Reason seems instead to suggest leaving while they can move to a
land where life seems possible. This is all the more true since Marc
André just learned that his plan for Africa has fallen through. Pascal,
then, looks upon Brazil as an opportunity to give his family, including
Esther and Marc André, a chance for a good life.
The last two acts take place in Brazil at the home of the Martinez.
The setting is a spacious living room that opens onto a patio.
When we arrive in Brazil, it is immediately and painfully clear that
the Laumières are considered refugees. They are expected to respect
the sensitivities of their host country and to follow the ways of its culture.
158
This behavioral compliance is requested in the name of politeness or the
common courtesy that is due in exchange for the hospitality they enjoy.
Expectations become increasingly oppressive, in both professional and
personal life. Compliance is, of course, expected of refugees. Pascal
feels undone. Marc André, by contrast, feels as if life has just begun.
Esther appears, carrying a letter with news of her brother, Robert, who
has disappeared. Probably he has been put out of the way because he
staunchly, perhaps even uncompromisingly, championed a "French"
communism.
Pascal and Esther discuss the death of Robert. They reminisce
about him, as if death let others see more clearly into his character.
Unloved, rejected by his mother, he forced everyone else to despise
him.
Renée and Carlos Martinez beg that no mention be made of
Robert'
s death, or of his communist affiliations. News of these would
create scandal among their friends. Carlos informs Pascal that his
weekly broadcast will be from the Martinez home, since Pascal
appears tired and somewhat weakened.
Pascal confides’ in Esther that curiously, almost paradoxically, the
scandalously persecuting manner of the Martinez’ and their priest friend
from the university gave him a vivid sympathy for Christ. as if behind the
threatening words of those torturers was an infinitely discrete appeal of
Christ, a distinct call--"not to betray." Later that same day, in sharp
contrast with the Martinez’ pagan priest friend, a young monk
approached Pascal. This young monk'
s face had the gentle look of
Christ'
s.(3)
Esther asks if Pascal has decided to submit. When he responds
that he definitely has not, she interjects that she, for her part, has decided
to return to France to care for Robert'
s baby since the infant'
s mother,
Robert’s mistress, wants no part of raising the child.
Marc André joins them, startled to see that his uncle doesn'
t look
well. Pascal comforts him, explaining that now he can make Professor
Moreuil'
s statement his own.
Pascal begins his weekly broadcast back to the people in France
with a quote from Sertorius, a Roman general in one of Corneille'
s
tragedies. Sertorius claims that "Rome is no longer in Rome" but instead
159
lives on in the hearts of those outside her walls who keep her heritage
alive.
Pascal cries out, "That verse is false. The claim is false." He
staggers but continues. "Stand fast. Stay.... And if you don'
t feel you
have the strength. Or if you think you won'
t have the strength." He
staggers and falls faint.
Esther runs to revive him. A young monk with a kind smile and a
gentle manner enters and moves toward Pascal. "Let me go to him. I
know he'
s waiting for me."(4)
The end of the play is stunning; its theatrical impact powerful. The
curtain falls, and the audience is left facing a darkened stage with only a
radio facing them.
We are surprised, disconcerted. We are left with questions that
call for reflection about the possibility of fidelity and the possibility of
communicating our values to others.
The play gives rise to many other questions about the different
characters and the significance of some of their actions and
interactions. The drama is artfully composed in a symphonic fashion,
and it would take a full-scale study to do justice to the intricacy of
meaning that is developed.
As the play ends, the question of the ultimate grounds for fidelity
when spiritual values are severely menaced is brought to mind by Pascal.
The finale of the play involves a reprise of the question
confronted by Professor Moreuil. This time, however, Pascal is ready
to answer that for him, ultimately one'
s fidelity to France, honor, liberty,
integrity, or a spirit of truth is founded in ones confidence in God'
s
fidelity. One'
s fidelity draws on a trust that God will not abandon those
who abandon themselves to his care, those who count on him as their
ultimate recourse. As Marcel wrote in Creative Fidelity, the foundation
of fidelity is faith in an Absolute Thou who is encountered as an
ultimate recourse in one’s dire distress. (5) Or, as Professor Moreuil
phrased it, he had confidence that in his hour of distress, be it trial or
torture, God would give him the strength to endure or would take his life
before he succumbed to betrayal.(6)
160
It was apparently this confidence in Christ, who as a personal
Presence can assure ones fidelity that founded Professor Moreuil's
decision to stay in France. A similar trust in the personal Presence of
Christ is what inspires and enables Pascal'
s decision not to be co-opted
by a repressive regime.(7)
That is why Pascal can say to his radio audience in France that
we live in a civilization where spiritual values are becoming more and
more alien. Stay--stand firm, be faithful and true--and if you do not have
the strength, be open in your hope for fidelity secured in the faithfulness
of a living God.
Abandoning pride, presumption, and stoic self-sufficiency, one can
find God as an Absolute Thou present in a moment of dire distress. God
comes then as our ultimate recourse.(8)
Perhaps our greatest strength comes when, in our weakness, we
draw on a strength that is other and more than our own.(9) Pascal'
s
decision and the message he broadcast, not to betray, is one that
expresses the mysterious and intimate workings of freedom and
grace.(10)
In the final moment of the play, and perhaps even of his life,
Pascals decision becomes really his own, an act he owns and through
which his life'
s meaning is expressed.(11)
By using four dots Marcel often leaves phrases and perspectives
of insight open-ended for the reader or spectator to inquire about and
then fill in with his or her own light. The pointing is "and if you have not
the strength...." Then there are the discrete stage directions. And then
the stark confrontation with the radio, inviting each one of us to hear and
consider the question ourselves.(12)
With dramatic power and discrete finesse, Marcel invites the
spectator to reconstruct the play and to discern for himself or herself
whether fidelity is possible, and whether ways can be found to
creatively incarnate it in our world today.
In the essay "The Real Issues in Rome Is No Longer In Rome,"
Marcel responds to some of the controversy stirred up by the play. He
points out that techniques of "brainwashing," first recognized because
of their prevalent use during the Korean War, changed the ground on
161
which valor, honor, integrity, or faithfulness are viewed. Prior to the fullscale
use of techniques of spiritual degradation or "brainwashing," the
stoic options could suffice. The stoic attitude is based on a confidence
or belief that the private regions of a person'
s mind and will were regions
that could not be violated, pressured, or altered. Patently mental and
psychic states can be altered. That is why one would be well advised to
write a declaration of one'
s stand compos mentis and a renunciation or
a retraction in advance of any statements conditioned by
brainwashing." Philosophically the question becomes: Is there
anything more trustworthy than human strength of mind, virtue, or
willpower when faced with forces of persecution whose techniques of
spiritual degradation are dehumanizing indeed?(13)
The action of the play illustrates various options that Marcel
evaluates concretely in the drama and examines philosophically in the
essays on fidelity in Creative Fidelity and Homo Viator. (14)
Morality appears inadequate to transmit values; otherwise Marc André
would surely have inherited the values of his mother, Esther.
Abstractions such as "honor," "liberty," "mankind," or "patriotism,"
though powerful sounding in propaganda, are of themselves inadequate
to ensure fidelity or to inspire creativity. Sterile arguments and abstract
notions do not move hearts or nourish lives, though they can be used to
feed emotions and to incite passions to promote fanaticism.
Fidelity is inspired by persons who communicate in love and in a
spirit of truth, as do for instance, Pascal, Esther, and Marc André. The
inspiration to fidelity is often through the person of someone present
from beyond death. The presence of Marc André'
s father from beyond
death certainly significantly influences Marc André, Esther, and also
Pascal.(15)
Physical force and psychological blackmail can pressure behavior.
Ideological propaganda can confuse thought and discourage feelings.
Political and social power can dictate ideological propaganda and force
behavioral compliance. Social control can be exercised by both totalitarian
Marxist governments and reactionary regimes of clericalism and very likely
by other groups as well. Although these forces and power groups can
dictate ideologies and manipulate behaviors, they are not enough to
control a person of liberty, an individual who lives in a spirit of truth.
162
Then what enables a person to resist the insidious and powerful
forces mentioned above; what can safeguard a person's fidelity?
Fidelity, in order to endure, like Pascal's, must be based on
interpersonal presence lived in a spirit of truth and love. Pascal cares
for his family, he cares with special concern for Marc André and Esther,
and he also cares for others in his literary and radio audience who
might try to live through this current crisis with integrity. Pascal,
together with Marc André and Esther, through open, searching
conversations tries to clarify what his responsibility is in living out fidelity
to the spiritual heritage of France.
Pascal’s fidelity is lived as an attempt to hear and respond to his
particular vocation.(16) His response is a commitment to the values of
life with honor. Pascal'
s fidelity is essentially animated and enlivened by
interpersonal relations with Marc André and Esther. In the trial of
persecution his fidelity is intensified. It deepens to the point that he
experiences an intersubjective relationship with God. Pascal’s fidelity
and its moment of fullest saturation are grounded finally in the
intersubjective presence of Christ.
As Marcel wrote in his essay "The real issues in Rome Is No
Longer in Rome," the play certainly does not suggest that there is only
one right way to preserve the honor of France. The play does not mean
to state bluntly that Pascal should have remained in France, nor does it
imply which is the right way to express faithfulness to the spiritual
values of France'
s heritage.(17)
Except for the case of Pascal, the play does not question
whether people's particular choices are expressive of their values. Each
person'
s choice is expressive of his or her values. Marc André wants to
be able to live, hope, and love. Esther,his mother, wants the best for
him, for Pascal, and later for Roberts child as well. Renée, on a more
practical and superficial level, wants a good life with all possible social
advantages for herself and her children. Pascal, moved by the
solidarity he senses with Marc André, feels responsible to provide the
children a better opportunity for life than the political and social situation
of France affords. Pascal judges his responsibility to be that of providing
for his household a situation wherein life is possible, He hopes at the
same time that he can also in some way remain faithful to France, his
homeland and heritage. Robert chooses to remain in France and
assure the reign of French communism when "the event" occurs.
163
People in the play do seem to question one another'
s values. There
is discussion for understanding. Pascal seems at times to deplore
Renée'
s expediency, but mostly he decries the way she demeans him,
almost incapacitates him. Renée in turn disdains and eventually
despises Robert’s ineffectiveness. Esther and Marc André seem to
encourage Pascal’s effort to be faithful to his integrity and purpose.
Only Robert and Pascal argue and condemn one another's positions.
Moreover, they try to undermine one another'
s confidence in their
values and in one another'
s abilities to effectively incarnate their fidelity
to those values.(18)
The conflict between Pascal and Robert not only shows the
opposition between their value systems, it also serves to clarify concretely
certain distinctions that are helpful toward developing a right
understanding of the challenge to incarnate creative fidelity to spiritual
values.
Ones effectiveness in responding to the challenge to incarnate
one'
s fidelity to spiritual values is not measured by ones success in
influencing socio-political trends. One'
s effectiveness in preserving
spiritual values and communicating them to others lies in ones ability to
awaken others awareness to the spiritual dimension of human dignity.
This awareness is something that is communicated among individuals in
a spirit of truth and love.
It seems that Robert's choice, which will help to assure "French"
communism when "the event" occurs, has the most likelihood of being
effective. His initiative is in line with socio-political forces. Robert will, it
appears, serve to assure a post-revolutionary survival of a French form
of communist government. But as Pascal foresees, Robert'
s initiative is
not likely to prevail. Those who gave Robert a formal promise of
French communism believe in dialectical truth that changes with the
circumstances. So when Robert’s tactics no longer serve to promote a
changing goal, he is disposed of. It is unlikely that any individual'
s
initiative will be effective in changing the direction of the socio-political
history of Western civilization. An individual action rarely can control the
force or the direction of socio-political trends. Neither Pascal'
s writing
nor Robert'
s direct action can reverse a trend that has gained so much
momentum. Social iniquity has gone too far.(19) Moreover, even if
socio-political trends could be altered, something more would be still
required to preserve and communicate values. Ideological propaganda
164
and behavioral conditioning can promote doctrinal orthodoxy and
behavioral social compliance. Force, physical or psychological, cannot
communicate spiritual values. These can only be espoused in liberty
and communicated in a spirit of truth that accompanies interpersonal
love.
Pascal's decision and the sense of it that is revealed dramatically
at the end of the play incarnate an authentic response to the challenge
for creative fidelity to spiritual values.
As Gabriel Marcel wrote in his philosophical essays, it is not others
or any critical public who can evaluate a person'
s fidelity.(20) It’s
oneself who is best suited to estimate the value of one'
s efforts. It is
oneself who can recognize the extent to which one'
s creation
corresponds to the original inspiration that gave rise to it. So it is Pascal
who can best judge whether his actions in the final scene correspond
to his deepest hope--not to betray but instead to preserve and transmit
what is most valuable in the spiritual heritage of France.
Upon reflection it appears that Pascal in the final scene has posed
an act of genuine creative fidelity. He has not betrayed. In his refusal
to go along with a repressive clericalism, he has preserved his sense of
honor and kept faith with what he esteems to be France'
s heritage of
spiritual values. Moreover, in the final and crucial moment of his ordeal,
the ultimate test of his fidelity, he has found that his strength to remain
faithful resides neither in resources of sheer willpower nor in the lifeless
ground of abstractions but in the lifegiving faithfulness of God present
to him through the person of Jesus Christ.
Pascal’s final decision has the characteristics of an act of
creative fidelity. His act of fidelity not only preserves the values of
his spiritual heritage for himself, but he also communicates them to
others. Pascal’s decision has an impact not only upon his life, but
on the lives of others as well. The decision is life-affirming,
especially for Marc André and for Esther. Marc André has begun to
live in this new world. Esther too has grown. She has let go of
Marc André and plans to return to France to care for her brother'
s
child, a child whose survival depends on her caring.(21)
Pascal communicates not only his deeds but also what he
lives by. He announces to people in France or wherever they are
in exile that their strength not to betray will come from beyond
165
themselves. Their faithfulness in time of trial in effect will be an
expression of the unfailing faithfulness of God. Pascal also
communicates what makes these deeds possible for him, namely
that because he has experienced the presence of Christ, seen his
face and heard his call through the faces and words of others, he is
assured that his attempt to live out his act of fidelity will be assured
by God's presence to him in his moment of distress. At the end
Pascal can make his own the words of Professor Moreuil that Marc
André had quoted to him earlier.
“I don'
t know what that moment will make of me, perhaps
a rag. I'
m not presuming on my own strength alone. I'
m
counting on God, that he will not abandon me, that he will
save me from a final disaster. Either he will take me to
himself, or he will give me the strength to withstand the
torture.” (22)
Pascal has shared the meaning of his action in conversation
with Marc André and Esther. They follow him with difficulty, and at
a certain point they can go no further. But, with time, especially
after his death, they will come to understand. Then his words will
become their own, as Moreuil'
s have become his. For Pascal’s
words are a witness. They are not just words he says, they are
words he supports with his very life and being.
A genuinely creative incarnation is one that is life-affirming
and one that lets traditional values be present in a new way
appropriate to altered circumstances. Certainly in this respect
Pascal's action is creative. His creative gesture springs from
resources of fidelity that are most deeply and intensely
interpersonal.
The genuineness of any act of creative fidelity is often indicated
by the additional acts of creative fidelity it inspires in other’s lives.
Whether or not this might be the case after Pascal’s plea is heard
depends upon the openness of Pascal'
s audience to hear his message
and the willingness of this audience in turn to reflect on the reality they
convey....
166
Notes to Chapter IX. Rome Is No Longer in Rome: Challenge for
Creative Incarnations of Fidelity
"Rome Is No Longer in Rome," has not yet been translated into English.
Still, the title is underlined in the text of this essay to enable readers to
easily recognize by the conventional sign that Rome Is No Longer in
Rome is the title of the play analyzed in this chapter. This underlining is
a departure from the system employed in Part Three of this book,
wherein titles in English are not underlined in order to indicate that a work
has not yet been translated and published in English.
1. Rome Is No Longer In Rome, a play in five acts and “The Real
Issues in Rome Is No Longer in Rome” to date have appeared
only in French: Rome n’ést plus dans Rome, pièce en cinq actes,
et “Les vrais problèmes de Rome n’est plus dans Rome”, Paris:
La Table Ronde, 1951.
2. Rome n’est plus dans Rome, Act II, Scene I, p.49.
3. Ibid., ActV, Scene V, pp. 142- 143.
4. Ibid., ActV, Scene V, pp. 147- 148.
5. Creative Fidelity, New York, Farrar, Strauss and Co., 1964, pp.
167, 182.
6. Rome n’est plus dans Rome, Act II, Scene I, p.49; cf. Act V,
Scene V, pp. 145-148.
7. Ibid., ActV, Scene V, pp. 142- 143.
8. Ibid., ActV, Scene V, pp. 49. ActV, Scene V, pp. 145- 148. “Les
vrais problèmes de Rome n’est plus dans Rome”, pp. 161-162;
Creative Fidelity, pp. 164-73, 182-832.
9. Rome n’est plus dans Rome, Act V, Scene V, p. 145.
10. “Les vrais problèmes de Rome n’est plus dans Rome”, P. 166.
11. Ibid., P. 165
12. Rome n’est plus dans Rome, Act V, Scene V, p. 148; “Les vrais
167
problèmes de Rome n’est plus dans Rome”, P. 153.
13, "Les vrais problèmes de Rome n’est plus dans Rome," pp. 160-
72, esp. 168-70.
14. Creative Fidelity, Ch. VIII, Ch. IX, pp. 147-74, 175-83; Homo
Viator, An Introduction to a Metaphysic of Hope, Chicago, Ill.,
Henry Regnery Co., 1951; New York, Harper Bros., 1962,
"Obedience and Fidelity," pp. 125-34.
15. Rome n’
est plus dans Rome, Act II, Scene I, pp. 51, 80.
16. "Les vrais problèmes de Rome n’est plus dans Rome," pp.
164-66.
17. Ibid., pp. 152-59.
18. Rome n’est plus dans Rome, Act II, Scenes I and II, pp. 67-
78.
19. Ibid., Act III, Scene I, p. 74.
20. Homo Viator, "Obedience and Fidelity," pp. 129-32.
21. Rome n’est plus dans Rome, Act V, Scene V, pp. 144.
22. Ibid., Act II, Scene I, p. 49.
168
Chapter X. Conclusion: Sketch of the Essential Features Highlighted
Reflection on eight Marcel plays and philosophic essays
commenting on the issues that the theater brings to light has enabled
us to highlight some of the essential features of "creative fidelity."
The Unfathomable lets us see that presence is central to a life of
creative fidelity. Presence consists of a spiritual exchange that can
become a life of intersubjectivity, a veritable co-esse. Edith'
s reflections in
The Unfathomable and Marcel'
s philosophic clarification in Presence
and Immortality enable us to recognize the nature of Presence. -
Presence occurs as a spiritual influx encountered by way of
inwardness and depth. These works also reveal Presence as a
witness of fidelity, a co-authored communion, the benefit of whose
renewals is always a mysterious incitement to create.
The two plays The Lantern and Dot the I reveal the essential role of
the light of truth in a life of creative fidelity. The Lantern shows that the
light of truth is an interpersonal Présence that enables one to discover in
truth what one loves and what it is that one hopes to live by. Dot the I
shows that existential witness discloses not merely ideas or the words
one says but also the very reality by which one lives.
The Lantern brings to light several essential aspects of creative
fidelity. Raymond'
s life shows what essays of philosophic reflection on
creative fidelity confirm. Creative initiatives issue from fidelity to the
Présence of loved ones in one'
s life. Genuine creativeness arises out of a
faithfulness to oneself. It springs from keeping in touch with what is
vital and most deeply personal, what is ultimately revealed only to love.
Such faithfulness to oneself is most often discovered, however, in
conjunction with one'
s attempts to remain faithful to one'
s family and
loved ones. Creative fidelity involves coming to know who one is in the
sense of recognizing and freely deciding what one wants to love and live
for. This self-discovery, a precondition to any genuine creativity, occurs
best in the radiance of a light of truth that is experienced as a personal
Présence.
Dot the I reveals how existential witness is an essential part of
creative fidelity. This play shows how one can communicate what one
lives by. In Dot the I Amy shows what her experience of forgiving and
169
of feeling assured that she is loved has been. Through compassion,
and love Amy the child becomes the mother of the woman. Amy
shares with Felicia not only the ideas she states but also the very
reality by which she lives. Amy’s testimony enables Felicia to begin to
experience within herself and in relation to her own life what it is that
Amy is talking about. Such communication of the interpersonal realities
that are part of our lives can only occur through a communion of love.
The Rebellious Heart highlights, by its absence in the life of
Daniel Meyrieux, what The Lantern portrays positively in the life of
Raymond Chavière. Creativity is not distinguished by novelty,
inventiveness, or spontaneity but rather by the fact that it is rooted in
faithfulness. Any genuine creativity in the realm of art or of daily living
requires as its basis faithfulness within a genuine communion of love.
Creativity finds itself resourced in faithfulness to oneself, faithfulness to
others, and ultimately in faithfulness to an absolute Other.
The Double Expertise leads us to recognize that creative fidelity,
like the act of commitment initiating it, has as its condition of possibility
availability, people's ability to invoke and provide actual renewals of
interpersonal presence and their effective and consecrated resolve to
do so.
The last three plays we considered, Colombyre or the Torch of
Peace, The Sting, and Rome Is No Longer in Rome, all portray the
contemporary situation wherein the survival of spiritual values is
threatened. This situation of menace highlights the heroic attitudes that
are necessary if human life is to survive.
Colombyre or the Torch of Peace shows the context that is
necessary if creative fidelity is to endure. For values to be realized, both
in the sense of being incarnately actualized and in the sense of being
personally understood, they must be expressed among persons. A
person-community whose atmosphere and one-to-one relations are
characterized by a spirit of light and love from above is the necessary
condition for the survival and growth of values. This context encourages
individuals to get in touch with their own personal experience and
heritage of values and to share this wealth with others. If spiritual values
are to be communicated effectively to others, it will be when the spirit of
light and love--the spirit that animates the one-to-one relations among
persons in community and that is reflected in their use of the things that
170
surround them - touches others by its radiance and by their existential
witness.
The Sting reveals that in our times, when spiritual values are
debunked and the very foundations of fidelity and trust are undermined,
what is called for is not mediocrity but heroic attitudes. Creative fidelity
requires the personal commitment and service of individuals who, like
the artist and the believer who really prays, are consecrated in selfsacrificing
love to quicken others'
sense of their spiritual dignity. Such
persons will be protected by their heroic commitment. Yet, given the
epidemic proportions of the malady of spiritual degradation that can
destroy an individual from within, they will also need to draw on the
self-sacrificing love of a martyr who lives on in them like a viaticum
nourishing and sustaining fidelity among the living. Creative fidelity calls
for heroic commitment. Creative fidelity also needs to draw on the
support of an interpersonal bond of love that unites us with those who
from beyond death assure the fidelity of the living.
Rome Is No Longer in Rome shows the situation wherein spiritual
values are so alien to a culture that any attempt to promote them or live
by them is almost sure to meet with violent persecution. In such a
situation it becomes clear that no individual can assure by his or her
strength alone that he or she will remain faithful through torture and
brain-washing. Assurance can only come in relation to a ground of fidelity
that can be experienced as one'
s ultimate recourse in response to an
appeal from one'
s utter distress.
Rome Is No Longer in Rome shows that it is of the essence of
creative fidelity to be resourced not merely in rational argumentation,
stoic constancy, or unswerving loyalty to abstract ideals, but in the
personal presence of God, whom we trust will not abandon and forsake,
but who will rather be faithful and save his people.
This play also shows that genuine expressions of creative fidelity
are not so much technical maneuvers that influence a socio-political
movement. Rather the concrete gestures that incarnate fidelity
creatively are personal acts of witness and testimony that, like Pascal'
s,
share with others in a spirit of truth and love the living core of one'
s
spiritual heritage.
171
Signs of the authenticity of one'
s acts of creative fidelity are that they
seem to awaken a sense of life in others and that they seem to
correspond to the original intent of their author.
Creative fidelity is centered in presence and is essentially a life
rooted in a communion of love. Creative fidelity is rooted in an
intersubjectivity of being that brings an uplifting of one'
s being and an
incitement to create whenever the conferral of presence is renewed.
Creative fidelity involves a light of truth that is the personal presence of
a loved one. The actual presence of a loved one, revealing what he or
she loves and live for, brings a light of truth that illumines one's own
discovery of what it is one hopes to be. The communion of love that
presence actualizes helps one not only to see, but also to decide in a
light of truth what one hopes to love and live by.
Creativity, with its striving for generativity, be it artistic or
human, is truly effective only when it finds its basis in a communion
of love involving faithfulness to oneself, faithfulness to others, and
ultimately faithfulness to an Other.
Faithfulness requires remaining in vital contact with what is
alive in oneself, that deep personal spiritual center that is revealed
only to love. Such faithfulness occurs and is often most readily
recognized in terms of one'
s response of faithfulness to another'
s
invitation and appeal for love.
A vow of creative fidelity is the voicing of a personal
commitment to be with and for another in loving care. It is also the
utterance of a hope and prayer that resources will be provided for us
to remain faithful in our reciprocal commitment to love.
The bond of love that is lived out as creative fidelity develops
through a dialogue of freedoms, an invitation or appeal, a free
response and a reciprocal resolve to be with and for one another.
The reciprocal self-gift of freedoms can progress from co-authoring
an I-Thou encounter to constituting a co-esse or intersubjectivity of
being that characterizes belonging and availability. This bonding and
commitment to be with and for one another is what constitutes a
communion of love. The pledge of its enduringness is what
formalizes and enables the life-long commitment of creative fidelity.
172
Creative fidelity, like the act of commitment initiating it, has as its
condition of possibility "availability," peoples ability to invoke and
provide actual renewals of interpersonal presence and their
consecrated and effective resolve to do so. Family or personcommunity
is the requisite context wherein creative fidelity, or a life of
commitment and service to promote human values with and for others,
can be lived out. In order for one's sharing of values to be authentic,
and not a farcical caricature, the interpersonal relations that
characterize the community'
s life must be animated by a spirit of light
and love from above. This inspiration incarnate in the community'
s oneto-one
relations is also reflected in the atmosphere of the community's
dwelling place and in its dealings with others.
Spiritual values or a reverence for the existential background of
human dignity are not transmitted best when broadcast like sound
waves from a transmitting set to be picked up by a receiving set.
Communicating values is rather a question of awakening in others their
sense of their worth as human individuals. Expressing toward others the
act of adoration addressed to the participation in the divine reality
within them can awaken in others their sense of divine filiation. This
communication is not so much a telling or even a giving of something as
it is a quickening of another's appreciation of his or her situation in
Being.
Creative fidelity may in fact simply designate an artful way of
living out a loving and life-long personal relationship with oneself,
others, and an Absolute Other.
There is a reciprocity in creative fidelity, one that is immediately
sensed and one that can finally be discovered to be ontologically
founded. It appears almost paradoxically. The creation of one's life as a
personal response to an invitation to be with and for others and an
Other is grounded in one's faithfulness to oneself, others, and an Other.
This faithfulness, as revealed poignantly in time of test or trial, is in turn
nourished by the faithfulness of others in their active communication of
love and by the faithfulness of an Absolute Thou as the ultimate
recourse and source of creative fidelity.
Sketching the main lines of the essence of creative fidelity risks
portraying as a bare-bones skeleton what in reality has all the concrete
richness of enfleshed individuals' lives.
173
Indeed, creative fidelity may be read as designating an
individual's response to a continually renewed call to be. The response
to that call is as creatively rich and varied as the individual’s life situation
and the particular invitations he or she received. In this perspective
creative fidelity may be recognized as a descriptive clarification of the
personal response and life story one writes as his or her answer to the
question "Who am I?"
Gabriel Marcel's book Du Refus à l’Invocation, entitled in English
Creative Fidelity, suggests that creative fidelity can denote a person’s
lifelong response to a continuous call to be. From this point of view it
becomes evident that the meaning of the term "creative fidelity,"
reflective of the mystery it expresses, transcends in richness any
particular expression or summary definition that might be given to it.
The purpose of this work is achieved if readers perceive a hint of
the richness of Gabriel Marcel's thought on creative fidelity, and if they
are at the same time attracted to explore his work and examine
firsthand the concrete richness of thought on this and other themes that
can be discovered there.
It is also my hope that this study has suggested, without betrayal
through oversimplification, how Gabriel Marcel's theater is a privileged
gateway into areas of inquiry that his philosophic reflections serve to
clarify.
The following section of this book offers information for those
wanting to know more about Gabriel Marcel.
174
There follow drawings by Stephen Healy depict the commemorative
medal commissioned by L'Hôtel des Monnaies (the National Mint of
France) and created by Charlotte Engels. One side presents a likeness
of Gabriel Marcel. The reverse side represents the myth of Orpheus
and Eurydice and bears the words fidélité, (fidelity); disponibilité,
(availability);and espérance, (hope). Marcel remarked that if he were to
choose mythological characters as a sign for his life he would choose
Orpheus and Eurydice. Certainly this choice highlights the centrality of
music in his life as well as his concern for loved ones who have passed
beyond death.
175
COMMEMORATIVE MEDAL OF GABRIEL MARCEL
Medal struck at La Monnaie
176
177
COMMISSIONED BY L'HÔTEL DES MONNAIE
For Présence De Gabriel Marcel
178
PART THREE: RESOURCES FOR RESEARCH
179
Works by Gabriel Marcel in Chronological Order of Composition with
Publisher References
A.Philosophical Works
(in chronological order of composition)
Les idées métaphysique de Coleridge dans leurs Rapports avec la
Philosophie de Schelling (1910) Coleridge et Schelling, (Présence et Pensée) Paris, Aubier Montaigne, 1971, 271 pp.
Fragments philosophiques, 1909-1914, Louvain, Editions Nauwelaerts,
1961. Philosophical Fragments, 1909-1914, Notre Dame, Indiana,
University of Notre Dame Press, 1965, 127 pp. English version
includes: Editors Note, “The Philosopher and Peace” by Gabriel Marcel,
“Foreword” by Gabriel Marcel, “Introduction” by Lionel Blain, “Philosophical
Fragments 1909-1914”, and “Epilogue” by Gabriel Marcel.
Journal métaphysique (1914-1923), Paris, Gallimard, 1927, Vol. XI, 341
pp. Metaphysical Journal, translated by Bernard Wall, Chicago, Henry
Regnery Company, 1952, Vol. XIII, 344 pp. English version adds
translator'
s note, p. v, and author'
s Préface to the English edition, p.
VII-XIII, 1950.
La Métaphysigue de Royce, Paris, Aubier, 1945, 225 pp. Royce’s Metaphysics, translated by Virginia and Gordon Ringer, Chicago, Henry Regnery Co., 1956, Vol. XVIII, 180 pp. English version includes
Préface by William Ernest Hocking, August 1956, p. V-VIII, Author'
s
Foreword to the English edition of Royce’s’
Metaphysic, July 1956, p. IX- XII. Reprinted 1975 by Greenwood Press, a division of WilliamhouseRegency
Inc.
"Position et approches concrètes du Mystère Ontologique" (1932) is
the text of a lecture delivered to the Philosophic Society of Marseille,
January 23, 1933. The essay was published in a volume with the play
entitled The Broken World, published by Desclée de Brouwer, Paris,
1933. The essay was later reprinted with an introduction by Marcel de
Corte and published by Louvain, Nauwelaerts, and Paris, Vrin, 1949. The
essay was again reprinted in the book Gabriel Marcel interrogé par
Pierre Boutang, Paris, J. M. Place, 1977, pp. 121-41, cf. p. 143. The
essay appeared in English translation by Manya Harari "On the
Ontological Mystery" in The Philosophy of Existentialism, Secaucas,
NJ, Citadel Press, pp. 9-46. Copyright 1956 The Philosophical Library.
A new English translation by Katharine Rose Hanley was published in
180
Gabriel Marcel’s Perspectives on the Broken World, Milwaukee, WI,
Marquette University Press, 1998, pp. 172-196. (Etienne Gilson
considers these pages as important to an understanding of Gabriel
Marcel'
s thought as is the Introduction to Metaphysics to the
understanding of Henri Bergson s thought.)
Etre et Avoir (1928-1933) Paris, Aubier, 1935, 357 pp. Being and
Having, Westminster, Dacre Press, 1949. Reprinted: New York, Harper and Row, 1965, Vol. XVII, 236 pp., with an Introduction to
the Torchbook Edition by James Collins, pp. VI-XVII.
Du Refus à L'invocation, Paris, Gallimard, 1940, 326 pp. Creative
Fidelity, translated with introduction by Robert Rosthal, New York, Farrar,
Straus, and Company, 1964, Vol. XXVI, 261 pp.; New York, Crossroad
Press, 1982, and New York: Fordham University Press 2002.
Homo Viator, Paris, Aubier, 1945, 358 pp. Homo Viator, Introduction to
a Metaphysic of Hope, translated by Emma Craufurd; originally
published in English by Victor Gollancz, Ltd., London, and Henry
Regnery Company, Chicago, in 1951 and reprinted through arrangement
with Editions Montaigne, New York, Harper and Brothers, 1962, 270 pp.
"Regard en arrière" in Existentialisme chrétien: Gabriel Marcel, Présentation de Etienne Gilson, Paris, (Présences), Plon, 1947, pp.
291-319. "An Essay in Autobiography," translated by Manya Harari,
Secaucus, NJ, Citadel Press, copyright 1956 by Philosophical Library, p.
104-28, in The Philosophy of Existentialism.
Le Mystère de lÊtre, I. Réflexion et Mystère, II. Foi et Realité, Paris,
Aubier, 1951, 235, 188 pp. The Mystery of Being, I. Reflection and
Mystery, II. Faith and Reality, Vol. I translated by G. S. Fraser, Vol. II
translated by René Hague, London, Harvill Press, 1951. Gateway
Edition, Henry Regnery, Chicago, IL, 1960. The Gifford Lectures,
delivered at the University of Aberdeen, Scotland, 1949. Reprinted
Lanham, MD, University of America Press, 1984.
Les Hommes contre l’humain, Paris, La Colombe, 1951, 206 pp. Man
Against Mass Society, translated by G. S. Fraser, Foreword by D. M.
Mackinnon, first published in Great Britain; A Gateway Edition, Chicago, IL,
Henry Regnery Company, 1962, 273 pp.
Le Declin de la Sagesse, Paris, Plon, 1954, 117 pp. The Decline of
Wisdom, translated by Manya Harari, London, Harvill Press, 1954, 56
181
pp., New York Philosophical Library, 1955.
L'
Homme problématique, Paris, Aubier, 1955. Problematic Man,
translated by Brian Thompson, introduction by Leslie Dewart, New York,
Herder and Herder, 1967, 144 pp.
"Le Crepuscule du sens commun," in one volume with La Dimension
Florestan, Paris, Plan, 1958, 212 pp., pp. 170-212.
Présence et immortalité, Paris, Flammarion, 1959. Présence and
Immortality, Pittsburgh, PA., Duquesne University Press; Louvain, Editions
Nauwelaerts, 1967, 284 pp.
182
Auf des Suche nach Wahrneit und Gerichtigkeit, (1959-1963), ed.
Wolfgang Ruf, Freiburg, im Bresgau, Verlag Knecht, 1964. Searchings,
New York, Newman Press, 1967, 118 pp.
La Dignité humaine et ses assises existentielles, Paris, Aubier, 1964.
The Existential Background of Human Dignity, The William James
Lectures, Delivered at Harvard University, 1961-62, Cambridge, MA.,
Harvard University Press, 1963.
"Le Philosophe devant la Paix," (1964), in Paix sur la Terre, deux
discours et une tragédie, Paris, Aubier, 1965, 177 pp., pp. 41-60. "The Philosopher and Peace" in Philosophical Fragments, (1909-1914) and
The Philosopher and Peace, translated by Viola Herms Drath, p. 6-19, Notre Dame, IN., University of Notre Dame Press, 1965, 127 pp.
Entretiens Paul Ricoeur-Gabriel Marcel, Paris, Aubier, 1968. Pour une Sagesse Tragique et son au-delà, Paris, Plon, 1971. Tragic Wisdom
and. Beyond, including Conversations between Paul Ricoeur and
Gabriel Marcel, translated by Stephen Jolin and Peter McCormick, Evanston, IL., Northwestern University Press, 1973, XXXV-p. 256.
Includes translators'
introductions and authors’ “Préfaces” for English versions.
"An Autobiographical Essay" (Spring 1969), in The Philosophy of Gabriel
Marcel, Library of Living Philosophers, Ed. P. A. Schilpp and L. E. Hahn, La Salle, I1, Open Court, 1984, XVIII, 624 pp., pp.3-68.
En Chemin, vers quel éveil? Paris, Gallimard, 1971, 301 pp.,
Awakenings, trans. Rev. Peter Rogers, S.J., Milwaukee, WI, Marquette
Univ. Press, 2004
"De l"Audace en métaphysique," in Percées vers un ailleurs, Paris,
Fayard, 1973, pp. 405-21.
Entretiens autour de Gabriel Marcel, "De la recherche philosophique" in Neuchâtel: à la Baconnière; Paris, Diffusion
Payot, 1976, 287 pp., pp. 9-19.
Gabriel Marcel interrogé par Pierre Boutang, Followed by Position
et approches concrètes du Mystère ontologique, (Archives du XXe
Siecle, no. 1), Paris, J. M. Place, 1977, 143 pp.
Présence de Gabriel Marcel, Cahier 4, Gabriel Marcel et les injustices
de ce temps, La responsabilité du philosophe. Cahier publié avec le
concours de la Fondation Européene de la Culture, Membership
subscription received at secretariat de la Présence de Gabriel Marcel,
21 rue de Tournon, 75006, Paris, France.
183
B. Gabriel Marcel's Plays
(In chronological order of composition)
La Lumière sur la montagne (1905). Unpublished.
Le Seuil Invisible. Paris: Grasset, 1914. Contains two plays: La Grâce (composed March-April 1911) and Le Palais de Sable (composed August-September 1913).
Le Quatuor en fa dièse. Paris:Plon, 1925. Written in 1916-
1917.
Un Juste. First act of an unfinished play written in early 1918 published in Paix sur la Terre, deux discourse et une tragédie, Paris:Aubier, 1965, pp. 61- 6.
L'
Insondable. First act of an unfinished play written March 1919, published in Présence et inmortalité, Paris: Flammarion, 1959, pp. 195-234.
Le Petit Garçon. An unpublished play in four acts written December 18-20, 1919.
Trois Pieces. Postwar 1919-1920, Paris: Plon, 1931. Contains three plays: Le Regard neuf, La Mort de demain, December 6-12, 1919; and La Chapelle ardente. (Several versions; 1949 edition contains revision and first version entitled Le Sol detruit. )
L'
Iconoclaste. Paris: Stock, 1923. Original idea, 1914, first draft, 1916
entitled Le Porte-glaive: written 1919-1920.
Le Coeur des autres. Paris: Grasset, 1921 (Cahiers verts). Written
1920.
Un Homme de Dieu. Paris: Grasset, 1925 (Cahiers verts). Written 1922;
New edition: La Table Ronde, 1950.
L'
Attelage ou le Noeud coulant. An unpublished play in four acts,
Written 1926.
L'
Horizon. Paris: Aux Étudiants de France, 1945. Written 1928.
Le Monde cassé, followed by a philosophic meditation entitled Position et
approches concrètes du Mystère ontologique. Paris: Desclée De
Brouwer, 1933. Written 1932.
184
Le Fanal, Paris: La Vie Intellectuelle (Supplement, 1936); Paris:
Stock, 1936. Written December 26-28, 1935.
L Chemin de Crête, Paris: Grasset, 1936.
Le Dard, Paris: Plon, 1936.
Théâtre comique. Paris: Albin Michel, 1947. Contains four plays:
Les Points sur les I. Written November 6-9, 1936. First published,
Paris: Fayard, 1938, in Les oeuvres libres No. 208, October, 1938.
Le Divertissement posthume. Written 1923. Colombyre ou le
Brasier de la Paix. Written 1937. La Double Expertise. Written
1936.
La Soif. Paris: Desclée De Brouwer, 1938. Re-edition entitled Les
Coeurs avides, Paris: La Table Ronde, 1952.
Vers un autre royaume. Paris: Plon, 1949. Contains L’Emmissaire, et
Le Signe de la Croix, 1949.
La Fin des Temps. Paris: Realités, 1950.
Rome n’est plus dans Rome, Paris: La Table Ronde, 1951. Mon
Temps n’est plus le votre. Paris: Plon, 1955. Croissez et
multipliez. Paris: Plon, 1955.
La Dimension Florestan. Paris: Plon, 1958.
La Prune et la prunelle. Paris: L'
Avant-Scène, 1960.
C. Translations of Gabriel Marcel Plays into English.
(In chronological order of composition)
The Unfathomable. March, 1919. First act of an unfinished play, L’'
Insondable. Trans. Michael A. Machado, Rev. Henry J. Koren, published, Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1967, Presence and
Immortality.
The Funeral Pyre. Original title of Rosalind Heywood'
s translation of
La Chapelle ardente (c. 1920) published London: Seeker & Warburg,
185
1952; paperback edition, New York: Hill and Wang, 1965: Three Plays has the translation of La Chapelle ardente entitled The Votive
Candle, pp. 225-82.
The Votive Candle. Revised title given to trans. of La Chapelle ardente
originally entitled The Funeral Pyre as above.
The Rebellious Heart. trans. by Francis C. O'
Hara, M.SS.A, of Le Coeur des autres, a play in three acts (written in 1920) in The Existential Drama of Gabriel Marcel, ed. F. J. Lescoe, West Hartford, Conn.: St. Joseph College Mc Auley Institute Press,
1974, pp. 145-215. New translation by Katharine Rose Hanley,
under the title “The Heart of Others”, in “The Path to
Peace”,forthcoming, Milwaukee: WI, Marquette University
Press, 200?
A Man of God. Trans. by Marjorie Gabain of Un Homme de Dieu, a play
in four acts (written 1922), published in Three Plays, London: Secker
and Warburg, 1952; New York: Hill and Wang, 1965, pp. 35-144.
Broken World. Trans. by J. M. P. Colla, R.S.M., of Le Monde cassé, a
play in four acts (written 1932) published in Existential Drama of
Gabriel Marcel, 1974, pp. 19-144. New translation by Katharine
Rose Hanley, Gabriel Marcel’s Perspectives on The Broken
World, Milwaukee:WI, Marquette University Press, 1998, pp31-
152.
The Lantern. Trans. by J. Cunneen and E. Stambler of Le Fanal, a one
act play (written December 26-28, 1935), Cross Currents, VIII, 2 (Spring 1958), pp. 129-43; Revised translation, in “The Path to
Peace”, M.U.P., forthcoming 200?.
Ariadne, translation by Rosalind Heywood of Le Chemin de Crete (written 1935) a play in four acts published in Three Plays, New York: Hill and
Wang, 1965, pp. 115-224.
Dot the I. Trans. by Katharine Rose Hanley (written 1936) in Two One Act
Plays by Gabriel Marcel, Introduction by Jean-Marie and Anne Marcel, Lanham, Maryland: University Press of America, 1986, pp. 1-21. Cf.
as above, “The Path to Peace”.
The Double Expertise._ Trans. by Katharine Rose Hanley (written 1937) in Two One Act Plays by Gabriel Marcel, Introduction by Jean-Marie and Anne Marcel, Lanham, Maryland: University Press of America, 1986,
pp. 23-38. Cf. as above “The Path to Peace”.
186
C. Drama Criticism
D. Gabriel Marcel'
s Essays in English on Drama and Relations of
Theater and Philosophy in his Work:
"The Drama of the Soul in Exile," Préface, pp. 13-34 in Three Plays. (A
lecture given in July 1950 at l’Institut Français in London.)
"My Dramatic Works as Viewed by the Philosopher" (1959), pp. 93-
118 in Searchings, New York: Newman Press, 1967.
The Existential Background of Human Dignity (The William James
Lectures, 1961-62). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1963, 178 pp.
Introduction to The Existential Drama of Gabriel Marcel, ed. F. J. Lescoe,
pp. 9-18, West Hartford, CT: McAuley Inst. Press, St. Josephs
College, 1974.
"An Autobiographical Essay" (1969) in The Philosophy of Gabriel
Marcel, Library of Living Philosophers Vol. XVII, ed. P. A. Schilpp & L. E.
Hahn. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1984, pp. 1-68.
E. Gabriel Marcel'
s Books of Drama Criticism in French :
Théâtre et Religion, Paris: Vitte, 1958, 107 pp.
L'
Heure Théatrale de Jean Giraudoux à Jean-Paul Sartre, Paris:
Plon, 1959, 230 pp.
Regards sur le Théâtre de Claudel, Paris: Beauchesne, 1964, 175 pp.
For additional essays published in French confer:
Chronological Bibliography of Works by Gabriel Marcel about his
Theater, pp. 39-42.
Drama reviews in periodicals are listed in Roger Troisfontaines, De
l’Êxistence à l’Être. La philosophie de Gabriel Marcel, pp. 385-464,
(1953; 2nd ed. 1968), Louvain, Nauwelaerts, Paris: Vr in.
Cf. Francois H. and Claire C. Lapointe: Gabriel Marcel and His Critics,
187
An International Bibliography, (1928-1976). New York and London:
Garland Press, 1977.
Also F. Lapointe, "A Bibliography of the Writings of Gabriel Marcel" in
The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel. The Library of Living
Philosophers, Vol. XVII, pp. 583-609 (1984).
188
E. Musical Compositions
Hommage à la Vie. (In Praise of Life), PP. 201-208.
Mes Manes à Clytie Music composed by Gabriel Marcel for a poem
by André Chenier. Appended in Marie-Madeleine Davy, Un
Philosophe Itinérant, Gabriel Marcel, (Homo Sapiens), Paris:
Flamrarion, 1959, p. 347.
Mélodie: Le Double. Music composed by Gabriel Marcel for a poem
by Jules Supervielle, pp. 321-24 in Existentialisme chretien: Gabriel
Marcel, présentation by Etienne Gilson, (Présences), Paris: Plon,
1947, p. 325.
Essays on Music Cahier 2-3, Présence de Gabriel Marcel
“L’Esthétique musicale de Gabriel Marcel,” par Jeanne Parain-Vial.
ARTICLES GENERAUX
Introduction: Gabriel Marcel et la critique musicale. Réflexions sur la
nature des idées musicales.
L'
idée chez Cesar Franck.
Bergsonisme et musique.
Musique comprise et Musique vécue.
La Musique et le regne de l’esprit.
La Musique selon St. Augustin.
Réponse a l
'
enquête de “L’Image Musicale."
Irruption de la Melodie.
La Musique et le merveilleux.
Méditation sur la musique.
Humanisme et musique.
La musique dans ma vie et mon oeuvre.
GABRIEL MARCEL ET L'
AUTRICHE
Les melodies espagnoles et italiennes d’Hugo Wolf.
Discours d’ouverture du Festival de Salzburg 1965.
L'
ECOLE FRANÇAISE
Un intimiste: Ernest Chausson.
Le lyrisme Debussiste.
189
Paul Dukas.
Henri Duparc.
Gabriel Fauré.
Cesar Franck.
Vincent d’Indy.
Albéric Magnard.
Maurice Ravel.
Albert Roussel.
DIVERS RÉFERENCES
Métaphores et exemples musicaux dans l’oeuvre de Gabriel
Marcel.
TEMOIGNAGE
Gabriel Marcel et le disque.
INDEX DES COMPOSITEURS CITÉS
I
INFORMATIONS
Subscriptions: Présence de Gabriel Marcel, 21 rue de Tournon,75006
Paris, France
Cf. L. Chaigne, Vie et oeuvres d'
Écrivains, Vol. 4, Paris: Lanore,
1954, pp. 252-53.
Hommage _ à la Vie. (In Praise of Life) is a copy of the piano
composition Gabriel Marcel improvised to bring J. Supervielle'
s poem to
its full expression as song. Gabriel Marcel improvised musical
compositions at the piano. His wife Jacqueline Boegner Marcel noted
the musical score for these piano compositions. This activity was
frequent and especially significant 1945-47. The sheet music for
Hommage à la Vie is reprinted here by kind permission of the family of
Gabriel Marcel.
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
Homage to Life
Words by JULES
SUPERVIELLE
Music by GABRIEL
MARECL
It is nice to have chosen
A living residence
And to house time
In a continuous heart,
And to have seen one'
s hands
Placed on the world
As on an apple
In a little garden,
To have loved the earth,
The moon and the sun,
As intimates
Which have no equals,
And to have entrusted
The world to one'
s memory
As a pale cavalier
On his black mount,
To have been friendly
To these concepts: wife, children,
And served as a shore
To wandering feelings,
198
Words by JULES SUPERVIELLE
Music by GABRIEL MARECL
And to have reached the soul
By small oar-strokes
Not to frighten it
By an abrupt approach.
It’s nice to have known
The shade under the foliage
And to have felt age
Creep over one’s nude body,
To have accompanied the pain
Of black blood in our veins
And gilded its silence
With the star Patience,
And to have all these words
Moving around in one’s head,
To choose the least loving
And celebrate it,
To have felt life
Premature and badly loved,
To have captured it
Into this poetry.
It’s nice to have known
The shade under the foliage
And to have felt age
Creep over one's nude body,
To have accompanied the pain
Of black blood in our veins
And gilded its silence
With the star Patience,
And to have all these words
Moving around in one'
s head,
To choose the least loving
And celebrate it,
To have felt life
Premature and badly loved,
To have captured it
Into this poetry.
Translated by
Janet Kawa and Judith Woodard
199
E. Combination Works by Gabriel Marcel
Books containing Works of both Theater and Philosophy (in
chronological order of composition)
Broken World and "On the Ontological Mystery" published together in
1933 in Le Monde Cassé, Paris: Desclée de Brouwer & Cie., 1933
(Collection Les Îles) followed by "Position et approches concrètes du
Mystère ontologique."
Le Dard et L’Universel contre les masses. Plon, 1936. Flammarion, 1951. (The Sting) and Man against Mass Society,_
Chicago: H. Regnery, 1952, 1962.
La Soif, followed by Gaston Fessard’s essay "Théâtre et Mystère," Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1938.
Rome n’est plus daps Rome et "
Les vrais problèmes de Rome n’est
plus dans Rome," Paris: La Table Ronde, 1951. (Rome is no longer in
Rome) and "The real issues of Rome is no longer in Rome," extract of
an article to appear in Hommes et Monde, presented by Gabriel Marcel
as an address May 18, 1951, at the Hébertot Theater.
La Dimension Florestan, Postface, "Le Crépuscule du Sens Commun" 1953-1954. (The Florestan Dimension) and ("The Twilight of Common Sense") and a Postface.
Présence et Immortalité, Paris: Flamrarion, 1959, contains
Metaphysical Journal 1938-43; essay, My Fundamental Purpose
(1937); essay Presence and Immortality (1951), originally entitled,
"On the Existential Premises of Survival," and The Unfathomable
(1919), the first act of an unfinished play.
Paix sur la terre, containing Un Juste (first act of an unfinished play)
and "Le philosophe devant la paix" (The Philosopher and Peace),
discourse pronounced upon the awarding of the Frankfurt Peace Prize,
Germany, 1964). Paris: Aubier, 1965, 177 pp.
Le Secret est dans les Îles, Paris: Plon, 1967, contains essay "Le
Secret est dans les Îles," Le Dard, L'
Emmissaire, La Fin des Temps. (The
Secret is in the Islands), contains a Preface by that title, the plays (The
Sting), (The Emissary), and (The End of Time).
Percées vers un Ailleurs, Paris: Fayard, 1973, contains Préface, L’ Iconoclaste, Commentaire de l’Abbé Belay, L’'
Horizon, Post face de
l’Horizon, Commentaire de l’Abbé Belay, essai "De L'
Audace en
200
Métaphysique.", (Daring in Metaphysics) by Gabriel Marcel in
(Breakthrough toward a Beyond). Contains two plays, (The
Iconoclast) and (The Horizon), a Préface to one and a postface to the
other, two commentaries by Marcel Belay, and an essay by Gabriel
Marcel, "Daring in Metaphysics."
Cinq Pieces Majeures. Un Homme de Dieu, Le Monde cassé, Le
Chemin de crête, La Soif, Le Signe de la Croix. (Five Major Plays:) A
Man of God, The Broken World, Ariadne, (The Thirst) and (The Sign of
the Cross) Paris: Plon, 1973. At the end of this book, Marcel noted that
he planned to reedit L'
Emissaire, (The Emissary), and to publish with it
an essay "La Philosophie de l'
Épuration" (1945) which until that date
(1973) had only appeared in a Canadian review. The essay "La
Philosophie de l’Epuration" appeared in Présence de Gabriel Marcel,
Cahier 4, Gabriel Marcel et les injustices de ce temps. La responsabilité
du philosophe, published with the sponsorship of the European Cultural
Foundation, Paris: Aubier, 1983, pp. 77-103. Subscriptions: Présence
de Gabriel Marcel, 21 rue de Tournon, 75006 Paris, France.
201
F. Bibliographies
Lapointe, Francois H., "A Bibliography of the writings of Gabriel Marcel,"
pp. 583-609, in The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, (The Library of
Living Philosophers, Vol. XVII),ed. P. A. Schilpp and L. E. Hahn, LaSalle,
IL: Open Court, 1984.
Lapointe, Francois H., "Bibliography on Gabriel Marcel," The
Modern Schoolman, Vol. 49, (November 1971), pp. 23-49.
Lapointe, Francois H. and Claire C., Gabriel Marcel and His critics,
An International Bibliography, (1928-76), New York and London:
Garland Publishing, Inc., 1977.
Troisfontaines, Roger, S. J., De lÊxistence à l’Être,
La Philosophie de Gabriel Marcel, Louvain, Nauwelaerts, Paris: Vrin,
1952 and 1968. Bibliography through 1964, Vol. 2, pp. 381-464.
Wenning, Gerald C., "Works By and About Gabriel Marcel," The Southern Journal of Philosophy,_ Vol. 4, No. 2, (Summer 1966), pp. 82- 96.
202
G. Partial List of Marcel Plays Staged and Produced
Information to update and add to this partial listing will be gratefully
received by the author, c/o Gabriel Marcel Institute of Existential
Drama, Le Moyne College, Syracuse, NY 13214
La Grâce
Grace
Le Coeur des
autres
The Rebellious
Heart
Le Regard neuf
The New Look
La Mort de demain
Tomorrows Dead
La Chapelle Ardente
The Votive Candle
The Funeral Pyre
Un Homme de Dieu
A Man of God
At the Théâtre Mathurins, by the Grimace
Company, Paris, 1921
At the Théâtre Grévin, by the
Canard Sauvage Group, Paris, 1921.
In English at Le Moyne College, Gabriel
Marcel Institute for Existential Drama,
November 10-12, 1975.
At the Ambigu, under the patronage of the
Escholiers, Paris, 1922.
At the Théâtre des Arts, then by the DeuxMasques,
Paris, 1937.
At the Théâtre des Jeunes Auteurs au Vieux
Colombier, Paris, 1925.
In English The Funeral Pyre at Newton
College of the Sacred Heart, Newton, MA.,
1961.
Presented by the Comédie de l’Est at the
Théâtre Montparnasse, June, 1949, and
extended to the Théâtre de l’Oeuvre where it
was performed for several months, 1949-50.
It was performed at Cobourg in Germany,
and in German at Munster, Westphalia. It
was also performed in England.
In English, Readers Theater versions were
performed at De Paul University, Drama
203
Program, February
1974, and at Le Moyne
College, Gabriel
Marcel Institute for
Existential Drama,
April 1978.
204
L'Horizon
The Horizon
Le Monde cassé
The Broken World
Le Fanal
The Lantern
La Double Expertise
The Double Expertise
Les Points sur les i Dot the I
Le Chemin de crête Ariadne
H. Centers of Research
Présence de Gabriel Marcel
21 rue de Tournon, 75006 Paris, France
Publication:
Présence de Gabriel Marcel, Cahier
address as above.
Cercle Gabriel-Marcel ????
Siege social:
Case Postale 67
Cap-de-la Madeleine, Quebec
Canada G8T 7W1
Publication:
Bulletin du Cercle Gabriel-Marcel, Revue
philosophique et littéraire. Published six times
a year since 1979. address as above.
205
Gabriel Marcel Theater Project, Dept of Philosophy, Le Moyne College, 1418, Salt Springs Rd. ,Syracuse,
New York 13214
English-Speaking Gabriel Marcel Society
Department of Philosophy
University of Current President:
Prof. Brendan Sweetman,
INDEX
abstraction, 20
abstraction, spirit of, 132, 144-45
antinomy, 6, 12, 15, 24, 129
Ariadne, 5
atheism, 132
authenticity, 119
availability, 61, 103, 119, 120, 123, 164, 166
Bach, Johann Sebastian, 4
Beethoven, Ludwig von, 4 being, 17, 55
Belay, Marcel, 12, 23
belief, believer, 133-34
belonging, 61, 119, 120, 123
Bergson, Henri, 29(n. 8)
betrayal, 122
brainwashing, 155, 165
Broken world, The, 5, 10, 11, 25
Chenu, Joseph, 23, 25
Christ, 154, 156, 159
co-esse, 60, 64, 120, 125, 163, 166
Colombyre or the Torch of Peace, 5, 129, 130-31, 135, 164
Comédie Française, La, 6, 77
commitment, 61, 103, 116, 117-18, 119, 121
communication, 15, 60, 69, 71, 89, 94
community, 129, 131-32
compassion, 9, 82, 93
concreteness, 20
concrete philosophy, 20
206
conscience, individual, 7, 16
creation, artistic, 6, 66
creative fidelity, 63, 65, 70, 71, 79, 83, 105-106, 123-24, 125, 129, 132,
135, 146-47, 157-68
Creative Fidelity 83, 100, 105, 113, 117, 118, 123, 131, 154, 155, 167
creative fidelity, as interpersonal Présence, 116-17
"Creative Vow as the Essence of Fatherhood, The," 103
creativity, 100-102, 103, 105, 106, 159, 163, 164, 166
"Dangerous Situation of Ethical Values, The," 129, 132-35
Dard, Le, see: Sting, The
Davy, M. M., 23
death, 18, 23, 55-59, 67, 69, 132, 142, 147
degradation, 145, 146, 155, 165
dehumanization, 144
desire, 67-68, 69
despair vs. hope, 18, 99, 100, 106
207
dialogue, 116
dignity, 17, 117, 132, 146
Dot the I, 89-94, 163-64
Double Expertise, The, 111-20, 124-25, 164
"Drama of the Soul in Exile, The," 12, 141
"Ego and Its Relation to Others, The," 21, 104
encounter, I-thou, 120, 123, 166
equality, 143
"Essay in Autobiography, An," 4, 25, 62, 63-64
Existential Background of Human Dignity, The, 89, 137, 141
existential witness, 14, 18, 89, 93, 163, 164
experience, 21
faith, 7, 16, 18, 84, 132
faithfulness, see: fidelity
family, 104
Fessard, Gaston, 14, 23, 25
fidelity, 7, 16, 65, 83, 105, 106, 117, 119, 122, 123-24, 154,155-56, 159,
163, 164, 165
forgiveness, 93
freedom, 9, 12, 14, 18, 71, 93, 106, 116, 117-18, 122, 135, 166
friendship, 68, 120, 123
Gallagher, Kenneth, 23
generation gap, 16
Gilson, Etienne, 29(n.8)
God, belief in, 154
God, in human situations, 165
God, in theater, 84
grace, 67, 71, 84, 133, 134-35, 146
Grâce, 5, 8
having, 68
Heidegger, Martin, 17
"Homage à la vie," see: "In Praise of Life"
Homo Viator, Introduction to a Metaphysic of Hope, 68, 100, 117, 122,
155
hope, 7, 11, 16, 23, 67-68, 69-70, 71, 121, 122, 125
human dignity, nature of, 17
Husserl, Edmund, 21
hypocrisy, 118
208
Iconoclast, The, 11, 24
immortality, 55, 58, 69, 70
incarnation, 68
Increase and Multiply, 5
infidelity, 7, 122
"In Praise of Life," 201, 203-209
interrogation, as a method, 21, 22
209
intersubjectivity, 23, 59, 60, 62, 64, 66, 67, 69, 70, 116, 120, 125, 163
Invisible Threshold, The, 9, 17
Lantern, The, 6, 8, 77-85, 163
light, 66, 81, 83-84, 89, 99, 133
love, 13, 18, 62, 68, 69, 94, 104, 105, 116-123, 134, 156, 164, 165, 166
lucidity, 6, 8, 9
Man against Mass Society, 137, 138, 141, 142, 143, 144, 146
Man of God, A, 6
marriage, grounds for, 111-25
Metaphysical Journal, 56, 58, 65, 69
metaphysics, 19
Miceli, Vincent, 23
Moeller, Charles, 23
Mozart, Wolfgang Amadeus, 4
music, 3-5, 19, 200-209
"My Fundamental Purpose," 56, 66
mystery, 11, 14, 16, 20, 21, 22, 24, 64, 70, 121, 137
"Mystery of Family, The," 21, 104
My Time Is Not Your Time, 5
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 142
"Obedience and Fidelity," 105, 113, 117, 124
"On the Ontological Mystery," 19, 24, 65, 105, 124
"Paradox of a Philosopher-Dramatist, The," 144
parenting, 103-104
peace, 16, 131
phenomenology, 21-22, 130, 133
philosophy,
and music, 3-5
and theater, see: theater, and philosophy
as personal, 17-18
concrete, not abstract, 20
neo-Socratic approach, 21, 71
pity, tragic 15
poverty, spiritual, 146
prayer, 122, 125
presence, 59-60, 61-71, 81, 120, 122, 124, 163, 165-66
Presence and Immortality, 19, 56, 58, 59, 60, 66, 67, 163
210
Presence, from beyond death, 7, 55-71, 83-85, 146-47, 156
Presence, interpersonal, 61, 83-84
Presence, I-thou, 62
propaganda, 143
Quartet in F#, 5
211
"Real Issues of Rome Is No Longer In Rome, The," 155, 156-57
Rebellious Heart, The, 10, 13, 97-106, 164
recollection, 21
reflection, 12, 15, 19, 21, 79, 84, 106, 129, 130, 160
relationship, I-thou, 120
responsibility, 70
revelation, 65
Ricoeur, Paul, 21, 23
Rome Is No Longer in Rome, 151-60, 164, 165
sacred, the, 4, 17
Scheler, Max, 142
Secret is in the Isles, The, 7, 23, 137, 138, 141, 148(n.2)
self-gift, self-disposition, 60, 62, 105, 118-20, 123, 125
“Sketch of a Phenomenology and a Metaphysics of Hope," 21
146-47, 156
Sting, The, 5, 137-47, 148(n.2), 164-65
stoic attitude, 155
suffering, 141
survival, after death, 7, 55-71, 83-85, 146-47, 156
"Techniques of Degradation,"
145
theater, 3, 5-19
and mystery, 14-15
and philosophy, 3, 15-19, 23-26, 77, 89, 106, 137, 141, 147, 168
comic, 112
existential, 129-30
"for a broken world," 9-12
of inquiry, 6, 13-14
of interiority, 8-9, 18
transcendence, 62, 63
Troisfontaines, Roger, 23
truth, as light, 77, 81, 84, 89, 93-94, 134-35, 163
unbelief, 18
Unfathomable, The, 5, 56-59, 61, 104, 163
values, 20, 29, 130, 132, 133, 134, 135, 137, 146, 151, 157, 158, 164,
166-67
war,
212
About the Author
Katharine Rose Hanley holds a Ph.D. degree from the Higher
Institute of Philosophy, Louvain University, Belgium, where she first met
Gabriel Marcel in 1955. She is a Professor of Philosophy at Le Moyne
College, Syracuse, New York where she has taught since 1961. Since
1975 she has been Director of the Gabriel Marcel Institute of
Existential Drama at Le Moyne. Professor Hanley has authored books and numerous articles on metaphysical topics and on aspects of Gabriel Marcel'
s thought. She has lectured to national and international audiences. Recently she
addressed the International Gabriel Marcel Society in Paris as well as
the Société Française de
Philosophie at the Sorbonne.
The author has for several years been involved in translating and
editing some of Gabriel Marcel'
s 30 plays for English-speaking
audiences and in producing some of these plays for stage and
television.
213
214